The Read Online Free
  • Latest Novel
  • Hot Novel
  • Completed Novel
  • Popular Novel
  • Author List
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Young Adult
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Various Works

    Previous Page Next Page

      the other; and upon the one it follows that it is desirable, while

      upon the other it follows that it is objectionable. The sequence,

      therefore, in the latter case also is direct; for the desirable is the

      contrary of the objectionable. Likewise also in other cases. The

      sequence is, on the other hand, converse in such a case as this:

      Health follows upon vigour, but disease does not follow upon debility;

      rather debility follows upon disease. In this case, then, clearly

      the sequence is converse. Converse sequence is, however, rare in the

      case of contraries; usually the sequence is direct. If, therefore, the

      contrary of the one term does not follow upon the contrary of the

      other either directly or conversely, clearly neither does the one term

      follow upon the other in the statement made: whereas if the one

      followed the other in the case of the contraries, it must of necessity

      do so as well in the original statement.

      You should look also into cases of the privation or presence of a

      state in like manner to the case of contraries. Only, in the case of

      such privations the converse sequence does not occur: the sequence

      is always bound to be direct: e.g. as sensation follows sight, while

      absence of sensation follows blindness. For the opposition of

      sensation to absence of sensation is an opposition of the presence

      to the privation of a state: for the one of them is a state, and the

      other the privation of it.

      The case of relative terms should also be studied in like manner

      to that of a state and its privation: for the sequence of these as

      well is direct; e.g. if 3/1 is a multiple, then 1/3 is a fraction: for

      3/1 is relative to 1/3, and so is a multiple to a fraction. Again,

      if knowledge be a conceiving, then also the object of knowledge is

      an object of conception; and if sight be a sensation, then also the

      object of sight is an object of sensation. An objection may be made

      that there is no necessity for the sequence to take place, in the case

      of relative terms, in the way described: for the object of sensation

      is an object of knowledge, whereas sensation is not knowledge. The

      objection is, however, not generally received as really true; for many

      people deny that there is knowledge of objects of sensation. Moreover,

      the principle stated is just as useful for the contrary purpose,

      e.g. to show that the object of sensation is not an object of

      knowledge, on the ground that neither is sensation knowledge.

      9

      Again look at the case of the co-ordinates and inflected forms of

      the terms in the thesis, both in demolishing and in establishing it.

      By co-ordinates' are meant terms such as the following: 'Just deeds'

      and the 'just man' are coordinates of 'justice', and 'courageous

      deeds' and the 'courageous man' are co-ordinates of courage.

      Likewise also things that tend to produce and to preserve anything are

      called co-ordinates of that which they tend to produce and to

      preserve, as e.g. 'healthy habits' are co-ordinates of 'health' and

      a 'vigorous constitutional' of a 'vigorous constitution' and so

      forth also in other cases. 'Co-ordinate', then, usually describes

      cases such as these, whereas 'inflected forms' are such as the

      following: 'justly', 'courageously', 'healthily', and such as are

      formed in this way. It is usually held that words when used in their

      inflected forms as well are co-ordinates, as (e.g.) 'justly' in

      relation to justice, and 'courageously' to courage; and then

      'co-ordinate' describes all the members of the same kindred series,

      e.g. 'justice', 'just', of a man or an act, 'justly'. Clearly, then,

      when any one member, whatever its kind, of the same kindred series

      is shown to be good or praiseworthy, then all the rest as well come to

      be shown to be so: e.g. if 'justice' be something praiseworthy, then

      so will 'just', of a man or thing, and 'justly' connote something

      praiseworthy. Then 'justly' will be rendered also 'praiseworthily',

      derived will by the same inflexion from 'the praiseworthy' whereby

      'justly' is derived from 'justice'.

      Look not only in the case of the subject mentioned, but also in

      the case of its contrary, for the contrary predicate: e.g. argue

      that good is not necessarily pleasant; for neither is evil painful: or

      that, if the latter be the case, so is the former. Also, if justice be

      knowledge, then injustice is ignorance: and if 'justly' means

      'knowingly' and 'skilfully', then 'unjustly' means 'ignorantly' and

      'unskilfully': whereas if the latter be not true, neither is the

      former, as in the instance given just now: for 'unjustly' is more

      likely to seem equivalent to 'skilfully' than to 'unskilfully'. This

      commonplace rule has been stated before in dealing with the sequence

      of contraries; for all we are claiming now is that the contrary of P

      shall follow the contrary of S.

      Moreover, look at the modes of generation and destruction of a

      thing, and at the things which tend to produce or to destroy it,

      both in demolishing and in establishing a view. For those things whose

      modes of generation rank among good things, are themselves also

      good; and if they themselves be good, so also are their modes of

      generation. If, on the other hand, their modes of generation be

      evil, then they themselves also are evil. In regard to modes of

      destruction the converse is true: for if the modes of destruction rank

      as good things, then they themselves rank as evil things; whereas if

      the modes of destruction count as evil, they themselves count as good.

      The same argument applies also to things tending to produce and

      destroy: for things whose productive causes are good, themselves

      also rank as good; whereas if causes destructive of them are good,

      they themselves rank as evil.

      10

      Again, look at things which are like the subject in question, and

      see if they are in like case; e.g. if one branch of knowledge has more

      than one object, so also will one opinion; and if to possess sight

      be to see, then also to possess hearing will be to hear. Likewise also

      in the case of other things, both those which are and those which

      are generally held to be like. The rule in question is useful for both

      purposes; for if it be as stated in the case of some one like thing,

      it is so with the other like things as well, whereas if it be not so

      in the case of some one of them, neither is it so in the case of the

      others. Look and see also whether the cases are alike as regards a

      single thing and a number of things: for sometimes there is a

      discrepancy. Thus, if to 'know' a thing be to 'think of' it, then also

      to 'know many things' is to 'be thinking of many things'; whereas this

      is not true; for it is possible to know many things but not to be

      thinking of them. If, then, the latter proposition be not true,

      neither was the former that dealt with a single thing, viz. that to

      'know' a thing is to 'think of' it.

      Moreover, argue from greater and less degrees. In regard to

      greater degrees there are four commonplace rules. One is: See

      whether a greater
    degree of the predicate follows a greater degree

      of the subject: e.g. if pleasure be good, see whether also a greater

      pleasure be a greater good: and if to do a wrong be evil, see

      whether also to do a greater wrong is a greater evil. Now this rule is

      of use for both purposes: for if an increase of the accident follows

      an increase of the subject, as we have said, clearly the accident

      belongs; while if it does not follow, the accident does not belong.

      You should establish this by induction. Another rule is: If one

      predicate be attributed to two subjects; then supposing it does not

      belong to the subject to which it is the more likely to belong,

      neither does it belong where it is less likely to belong; while if

      it does belong where it is less likely to belong, then it belongs as

      well where it is more likely. Again: If two predicates be attributed

      to one subject, then if the one which is more generally thought to

      belong does not belong, neither does the one that is less generally

      thought to belong; or, if the one that is less generally thought to

      belong does belong, so also does the other. Moreover: If two

      predicates be attributed to two subjects, then if the one which is

      more usually thought to belong to the one subject does not belong,

      neither does the remaining predicate belong to the remaining

      subject; or, if the one which is less usually thought to belong to the

      one subject does belong, so too does the remaining predicate to the

      remaining subject.

      Moreover, you can argue from the fact that an attribute belongs,

      or is generally supposed to belong, in a like degree, in three ways,

      viz. those described in the last three rules given in regard to a

      greater degree.' For supposing that one predicate belongs, or is

      supposed to belong, to two subjects in a like degree, then if it

      does not belong to the one, neither does it belong to the other; while

      if it belongs to the one, it belongs to the remaining one as well. Or,

      supposing two predicates to belong in a like degree to the same

      subject, then, if the one does not belong, neither does the

      remaining one; while if the one does belong, the remaining one belongs

      as well. The case is the same also if two predicates belong in a

      like degree to two subjects; for if the one predicate does not

      belong to the one subject, neither does the remaining predicate belong

      to the remaining subject, while if the one predicate does belong to

      the one subject, the remaining predicate belongs to the remaining

      subject as well.

      11

      You can argue, then, from greater or less or like degrees of truth

      in the aforesaid number of ways. Moreover, you should argue from the

      addition of one thing to another. If the addition of one thing to

      another makes that other good or white, whereas formerly it was not

      white or good, then the thing added will be white or good-it will

      possess the character it imparts to the whole as well. Moreover, if an

      addition of something to a given object intensifies the character

      which it had as given, then the thing added will itself as well be

      of that character. Likewise, also, in the case of other attributes.

      The rule is not applicable in all cases, but only in those in which

      the excess described as an 'increased intensity' is found to take

      place. The above rule is, however, not convertible for overthrowing

      a view. For if the thing added does not make the other good, it is not

      thereby made clear whether in itself it may not be good: for the

      addition of good to evil does not necessarily make the whole good, any

      more than the addition of white to black makes the whole white.

      Again, any predicate of which we can speak of greater or less

      degrees belongs also absolutely: for greater or less degrees of good

      or of white will not be attributed to what is not good or white: for a

      bad thing will never be said to have a greater or less degree of

      goodness than another, but always of badness. This rule is not

      convertible, either, for the purpose of overthrowing a predication:

      for several predicates of which we cannot speak of a greater degree

      belong absolutely: for the term 'man' is not attributed in greater and

      less degrees, but a man is a man for all that.

      You should examine in the same way predicates attributed in a

      given respect, and at a given time and place: for if the predicate

      be possible in some respect, it is possible also absolutely. Likewise,

      also, is what is predicated at a given time or place: for what is

      absolutely impossible is not possible either in any respect or at

      any place or time. An objection may be raised that in a given

      respect people may be good by nature, e.g. they may be generous or

      temperately inclined, while absolutely they are not good by nature,

      because no one is prudent by nature. Likewise, also, it is possible

      for a destructible thing to escape destruction at a given time,

      whereas it is not possible for it to escape absolutely. In the same

      way also it is a good thing at certain places to follow see and such a

      diet, e.g. in infected areas, though it is not a good thing

      absolutely. Moreover, in certain places it is possible to live

      singly and alone, but absolutely it is not possible to exist singly

      and alone. In the same way also it is in certain places honourable

      to sacrifice one's father, e.g. among the Triballi, whereas,

      absolutely, it is not honourable. Or possibly this may indicate a

      relativity not to places but to persons: for it is all the same

      wherever they may be: for everywhere it will be held honourable

      among the Triballi themselves, just because they are Triballi.

      Again, at certain times it is a good thing to take medicines, e.g.

      when one is ill, but it is not so absolutely. Or possibly this again

      may indicate a relativity not to a certain time, but to a certain

      state of health: for it is all the same whenever it occurs, if only

      one be in that state. A thing is 'absolutely' so which without any

      addition you are prepared to say is honourable or the contrary. Thus

      (e.g.) you will deny that to sacrifice one's father is honourable:

      it is honourable only to certain persons: it is not therefore

      honourable absolutely. On the other hand, to honour the gods you

      will declare to be honourable without adding anything, because that is

      honourable absolutely. So that whatever without any addition is

      generally accounted to be honourable or dishonourable or anything else

      of that kind, will be said to be so 'absolutely'.

      Book III

      1

      THE question which is the more desirable, or the better, of two or

      more things, should be examined upon the following lines: only first

      of all it must be clearly laid down that the inquiry we are making

      concerns not things that are widely divergent and that exhibit great

      differences from one another (for nobody raises any doubt whether

      happiness or wealth is more desirable), but things that are nearly

      related and about which we commonly discuss for which of the two we

      ought rather to vote, because we do not see any advantage on either
    br />   side as compared with the other. Clearly, in such cases if we can show

      a single advantage, or more than one, our judgement will record our

      assent that whichever side happens to have the advantage is the more

      desirable.

      First, then, that which is more lasting or secure is more

      desirable than that which is less so: and so is that which is more

      likely to be chosen by the prudent or by the good man or by the

      right law, or by men who are good in any particular line, when they

      make their choice as such, or by the experts in regard to any

      particular class of things; i.e. either whatever most of them or

      what all of them would choose; e.g. in medicine or in carpentry

      those things are more desirable which most, or all, doctors would

      choose; or, in general, whatever most men or all men or all things

      would choose, e.g. the good: for everything aims at the good. You

      should direct the argument you intend to employ to whatever purpose

      you require. Of what is 'better' or 'more desirable' the absolute

      standard is the verdict of the better science, though relatively to

      a given individual the standard may be his own particular science.

      In the second place, that which is known as 'an x' is more desirable

      than that which does not come within the genus 'x'-e.g. justice than a

      just man; for the former falls within the genus 'good', whereas the

      other does not, and the former is called 'a good', whereas the

      latter is not: for nothing which does not happen to belong to the

      genus in question is called by the generic name; e.g. a 'white man' is

      not 'a colour'. Likewise also in other cases.

      Also, that which is desired for itself is more desirable than that

      which is desired for something else; e.g. health is more desirable

      than gymnastics: for the former is desired for itself, the latter

      for something else. Also, that which is desirable in itself is more

      desirable than what is desirable per accidens; e.g. justice in our

      friends than justice in our enemies: for the former is desirable in

      itself, the latter per accidens: for we desire that our enemies should

     
    Previous Page Next Page
© The Read Online Free 2022~2025