The Read Online Free
  • Latest Novel
  • Hot Novel
  • Completed Novel
  • Popular Novel
  • Author List
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Young Adult
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Various Works

    Previous Page Next Page

      4

      Comparisons of things together should therefore be conducted in

      the manner prescribed. The same commonplace rules are useful also

      for showing that anything is simply desirable or objectionable: for we

      have only to subtract the excess of one thing over another. For if

      what is more precious be more desirable, then also what is precious is

      desirable; and if what is more useful be more desirable, then also

      what is useful is desirable. Likewise, also, in the case of other

      things which admit of comparisons of that kind. For in some cases in

      the very course of comparing the things together we at once assert

      also that each of them, or the one of them, is desirable, e.g.

      whenever we call the one good 'by nature' and the other 'not by

      nature': for dearly what is good by nature is desirable.

      5

      The commonplace rules relating to comparative degrees and amounts

      ought to be taken in the most general possible form: for when so taken

      they are likely to be useful in a larger number of instances. It is

      possible to render some of the actual rules given above more universal

      by a slight alteration of the expression, e.g. that what by nature

      exhibits such and such a quality exhibits that quality in a greater

      degree than what exhibits it not by nature. Also, if one thing does,

      and another does not, impart such and such a quality to that which

      possesses it, or to which it belongs, then whichever does impart it is

      of that quality in greater degree than the one which does not impart

      it; and if both impart it, then that one exhibits it in a greater

      degree which imparts it in a greater degree.

      Moreover, if in any character one thing exceeds and another falls

      short of the same standard; also, if the one exceeds something which

      exceeds a given standard, while the other does not reach that

      standard, then clearly the first-named thing exhibits that character

      in a greater degree. Moreover, you should judge by means of

      addition, and see if A when added to the same thing as B imparts to

      the whole such and such a character in a more marked degree than B, or

      if, when added to a thing which exhibits that character in a less

      degree, it imparts that character to the whole in a greater degree.

      Likewise, also, you may judge by means of subtraction: for a thing

      upon whose subtraction the remainder exhibits such and such a

      character in a less degree, itself exhibits that character in a

      greater degree. Also, things exhibit such and such a character in a

      greater degree if more free from admixture with their contraries; e.g.

      that is whiter which is more free from admixture with black. Moreover,

      apart from the rules given above, that has such and such a character

      in greater degree which admits in a greater degree of the definition

      proper to the given character; e.g. if the definition of 'white' be 'a

      colour which pierces the vision', then that is whiter which is in a

      greater degree a colour that pierces the vision.

      6

      If the question be put in a particular and not in a universal

      form, in the first place the universal constructive or destructive

      commonplace rules that have been given may all be brought into use.

      For in demolishing or establishing a thing universally we also show it

      in particular: for if it be true of all, it is true also of some,

      and if untrue of all, it is untrue of some. Especially handy and of

      general application are the commonplace rules that are drawn from

      the opposites and co-ordinates and inflexions of a thing: for public

      opinion grants alike the claim that if all pleasure be good, then also

      all pain is evil, and the claim that if some pleasure be good, then

      also some pain is evil. Moreover, if some form of sensation be not a

      capacity, then also some form of failure of sensation is not a failure

      of capacity. Also, if the object of conception is in some cases an

      object of knowledge, then also some form of conceiving is knowledge.

      Again, if what is unjust be in some cases good, then also what is just

      is in some cases evil; and if what happens justly is in some cases

      evil, then also what happens unjustly is in some cases good. Also,

      if what is pleasant is in some cases objectionable, then pleasure is

      in some cases an objectionable thing. On the same principle, also,

      if what is pleasant is in some cases beneficial, then pleasure is in

      some cases a beneficial thing. The case is the same also as regards

      the things that destroy, and the processes of generation and

      destruction. For if anything that destroys pleasure or knowledge be in

      some cases good, then we may take it that pleasure or knowledge is

      in some cases an evil thing. Likewise, also, if the destruction of

      knowledge be in some cases a good thing or its production an evil

      thing, then knowledge will be in some cases an evil thing; e.g. if for

      a man to forget his disgraceful conduct be a good thing, and to

      remember it be an evil thing, then the knowledge of his disgraceful

      conduct may be taken to be an evil thing. The same holds also in other

      cases: in all such cases the premiss and the conclusion are equally

      likely to be accepted.

      Moreover you should judge by means of greater or smaller or like

      degrees: for if some member of another genus exhibit such and such a

      character in a more marked degree than your object, while no member of

      that genus exhibits that character at all, then you may take it that

      neither does the object in question exhibit it; e.g. if some form of

      knowledge be good in a greater degree than pleasure, while no form

      of knowledge is good, then you may take it that pleasure is not good

      either. Also, you should judge by a smaller or like degree in the same

      way: for so you will find it possible both to demolish and to

      establish a view, except that whereas both are possible by means of

      like degrees, by means of a smaller degree it is possible only to

      establish, not to overthrow. For if a certain form of capacity be good

      in a like degree to knowledge, and a certain form of capacity be good,

      then so also is knowledge; while if no form of capacity be good,

      then neither is knowledge. If, too, a certain form of capacity be good

      in a less degree than knowledge, and a certain form of capacity be

      good, then so also is knowledge; but if no form of capacity be good,

      there is no necessity that no form of knowledge either should be good.

      Clearly, then, it is only possible to establish a view by means of a

      less degree.

      Not only by means of another genus can you overthrow a view, but

      also by means of the same, if you take the most marked instance of the

      character in question; e.g. if it be maintained that some form of

      knowledge is good, then, suppose it to be shown that prudence is not

      good, neither will any other kind be good, seeing that not even the

      kind upon which there is most general agreement is so. Moreover, you

      should go to work by means of an hypothesis; you should claim that the

      attribute, if it belongs or does not belong in one case, does so in

      a like degree in all, e.g. that if t
    he soul of man be immortal, so are

      other souls as well, while if this one be not so, neither are the

      others. If, then, it be maintained that in some instance the attribute

      belongs, you must show that in some instance it does not belong: for

      then it will follow, by reason of the hypothesis, that it does not

      belong to any instance at all. If, on the other hand, it be maintained

      that it does not belong in some instance, you must show that it does

      belong in some instance, for in this way it will follow that it

      belongs to all instances. It is clear that the maker of the hypothesis

      universalizes the question, whereas it was stated in a particular

      form: for he claims that the maker of a particular admission should

      make a universal admission, inasmuch as he claims that if the

      attribute belongs in one instance, it belongs also in all instances

      alike.

      If the problem be indefinite, it is possible to overthrow a

      statement in only one way; e.g. if a man has asserted that pleasure is

      good or is not good, without any further definition. For if he meant

      that a particular pleasure is good, you must show universally that

      no pleasure is good, if the proposition in question is to be

      demolished. And likewise, also, if he meant that some particular

      pleasure is not good you must show universally that all pleasure is

      good: it is impossible to demolish it in any other way. For if we show

      that some particular pleasure is not good or is good, the

      proposition in question is not yet demolished. It is clear, then, that

      it is possible to demolish an indefinite statement in one way only,

      whereas it can be established in two ways: for whether we show

      universally that all pleasure is good, or whether we show that a

      particular pleasure is good, the proposition in question will have

      been proved. Likewise, also, supposing we are required to argue that

      some particular pleasure is not good, if we show that no pleasure is

      good or that a particular pleasure is not good, we shall have produced

      an argument in both ways, both universally and in particular, to

      show that some particular pleasure is not good. If, on the other hand,

      the statement made be definite, it will be possible to demolish it

      in two ways; e.g. if it be maintained that it is an attribute of

      some particular pleasure to be good, while of some it is not: for

      whether it be shown that all pleasure, or that no pleasure, is good,

      the proposition in question will have been demolished. If, however, he

      has stated that only one single pleasure is good, it is possible to

      demolish it in three ways: for by showing that all pleasure, or that

      no pleasure, or that more than one pleasure, is good, we shall have

      demolished the statement in question. If the statement be made still

      more definite, e.g. that prudence alone of the virtues is knowledge,

      there are four ways of demolishing it: for if it be shown that all

      virtue is knowledge, or that no virtue is so, or that some other

      virtue (e.g. justice) is so, or that prudence itself is not knowledge,

      the proposition in question will have been demolished.

      It is useful also to take a look at individual instances, in cases

      where some attribute has been said to belong or not to belong, as in

      the case of universal questions. Moreover, you should take a glance

      among genera, dividing them by their species until you come to those

      that are not further divisible, as has been said before:' for

      whether the attribute is found to belong in all cases or in none,

      you should, after adducing several instances, claim that he should

      either admit your point universally, or else bring an objection

      showing in what case it does not hold. Moreover, in cases where it

      is possible to make the accident definite either specifically or

      numerically, you should look and see whether perhaps none of them

      belongs, showing e.g. that time is not moved, nor yet a movement, by

      enumerating how many species there are of movement: for if none of

      these belong to time, clearly it does not move, nor yet is a movement.

      Likewise, also, you can show that the soul is not a number, by

      dividing all numbers into either odd or even: for then, if the soul be

      neither odd nor even, clearly it is not a number.

      In regard then to Accident, you should set to work by means like

      these, and in this manner.

      Book IV

      1

      NEXT we must go on to examine questions relating to Genus and

      Property. These are elements in the questions that relate to

      definitions, but dialecticians seldom address their inquiries to these

      by themselves. If, then, a genus be suggested for something that is,

      first take a look at all objects which belong to the same genus as the

      thing mentioned, and see whether the genus suggested is not predicated

      of one of them, as happens in the case of an accident: e.g. if

      'good' be laid down to be the genus of 'pleasure', see whether some

      particular pleasure be not good: for, if so, clearly good' is not

      the genus of pleasure: for the genus is predicated of all the

      members of the same species. Secondly, see whether it be predicated

      not in the category of essence, but as an accident, as 'white' is

      predicated of 'snow', or 'self-moved' of the soul. For 'snow' is not a

      kind of 'white', and therefore 'white' is not the genus of snow, nor

      is the soul a kind of 'moving object': its motion is an accident of

      it, as it often is of an animal to walk or to be walking. Moreover,

      'moving' does not seem to indicate the essence, but rather a state

      of doing or of having something done to it. Likewise, also, 'white':

      for it indicates not the essence of snow, but a certain quality of it.

      So that neither of them is predicated in the category of 'essence'.

      Especially you should take a look at the definition of Accident, and

      see whether it fits the genus mentioned, as (e.g.) is also the case in

      the instances just given. For it is possible for a thing to be and not

      to be self-moved, and likewise, also, for it to be and not to be

      white. So that neither of these attributes is the genus but an

      accident, since we were saying that an accident is an attribute

      which can belong to a thing and also not belong.

      Moreover, see whether the genus and the species be not found in

      the same division, but the one be a substance while the other is a

      quality, or the one be a relative while the other is a quality, as

      (e.g.) 'slow' and 'swan' are each a substance, while 'white' is not

      a substance but a quality, so that 'white' is not the genus either

      of 'snow' or of 'swan'. Again, knowledge' is a relative, while

      'good' and 'noble' are each a quality, so that good, or noble, is

      not the genus of knowledge. For the genera of relatives ought

      themselves also to be relatives, as is the case with 'double': for

      multiple', which is the genus of 'double', is itself also a

      relative. To speak generally, the genus ought to fall under the same

      division as the species: for if the species be a substance, so too

      should be the genus, and if the species be a quality, so too the genus

      shou
    ld be a quality; e.g. if white be a quality, so too should

      colour be. Likewise, also, in other cases.

      Again, see whether it be necessary or possible for the genus to

      partake of the object which has been placed in the genus. 'To partake'

      is defined as 'to admit the definition of that which is partaken.

      Clearly, therefore, the species partake of the genera, but not the

      genera of the species: for the species admits the definition of the

      genus, whereas the genus does not admit that of the species. You

      must look, therefore, and see whether the genus rendered partakes or

      can possibly partake of the species, e.g. if any one were to render

      anything as genus of 'being' or of 'unity': for then the result will

      be that the genus partakes of the species: for of everything that

      is, 'being' and 'unity' are predicated, and therefore their definition

      as well.

      Moreover, see if there be anything of which the species rendered

      is true, while the genus is not so, e.g. supposing 'being' or

      'object of knowledge' were stated to be the genus of 'object of

      opinion'. For 'object of opinion' will be a predicate of what does not

      exist; for many things which do not exist are objects of opinion;

      whereas that 'being' or 'object of knowledge' is not predicated of

      what does not exist is clear. So that neither 'being' nor 'object of

      knowledge' is the genus of 'object of opinion': for of the objects

      of which the species is predicated, the genus ought to be predicated

      as well.

      Again, see whether the object placed in the genus be quite unable to

      partake of any of its species: for it is impossible that it should

      partake of the genus if it do not partake of any of its species,

      except it be one of the species reached by the first division: these

      do partake of the genus alone. If, therefore, 'Motion' be stated as

      the genus of pleasure, you should look and see if pleasure be

      neither locomotion nor alteration, nor any of the rest of the given

      modes of motion: for clearly you may then take it that it does not

      partake of any of the species, and therefore not of the genus

     
    Previous Page Next Page
© The Read Online Free 2022~2025