The Read Online Free
  • Latest Novel
  • Hot Novel
  • Completed Novel
  • Popular Novel
  • Author List
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Young Adult
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Various Works

    Previous Page Next Page

      that those who define in this way cannot show the essential nature

      of the term they define, unless it so happens that the same thing is

      more intelligible both to us and also absolutely, since a correct

      definition must define a thing through its genus and its differentiae,

      and these belong to the order of things which are absolutely more

      intelligible than, and prior to, the species. For annul the genus

      and differentia, and the species too is annulled, so that these are

      prior to the species. They are also more intelligible; for if the

      species be known, the genus and differentia must of necessity be known

      as well (for any one who knows what a man is knows also what

      'animal' and 'walking' are), whereas if the genus or the differentia

      be known it does not follow of necessity that the species is known

      as well: thus the species is less intelligible. Moreover, those who

      say that such definitions, viz. those which proceed from what is

      intelligible to this, that, or the other man, are really and truly

      definitions, will have to say that there are several definitions of

      one and the same thing. For, as it happens, different things are

      more intelligible to different people, not the same things to all; and

      so a different definition would have to be rendered to each several

      person, if the definition is to be constructed from what is more

      intelligible to particular individuals. Moreover, to the same people

      different things are more intelligible at different times; first of

      all the objects of sense; then, as they become more sharpwitted, the

      converse; so that those who hold that a definition ought to be

      rendered through what is more intelligible to particular individuals

      would not have to render the same definition at all times even to

      the same person. It is clear, then, that the right way to define is

      not through terms of that kind, but through what is absolutely more

      intelligible: for only in this way could the definition come always to

      be one and the same. Perhaps, also, what is absolutely intelligible is

      what is intelligible, not to all, but to those who are in a sound

      state of understanding, just as what is absolutely healthy is what

      is healthy to those in a sound state of body. All such points as

      this ought to be made very precise, and made use of in the course of

      discussion as occasion requires. The demolition of a definition will

      most surely win a general approval if the definer happens to have

      framed his expression neither from what is absolutely more

      intelligible nor yet from what is so to us.

      One form, then, of the failure to work through more intelligible

      terms is the exhibition of the prior through the posterior, as we

      remarked before.' Another form occurs if we find that the definition

      has been rendered of what is at rest and definite through what is

      indefinite and in motion: for what is still and definite is prior to

      what is indefinite and in motion.

      Of the failure to use terms that are prior there are three forms:

      (1) The first is when an opposite has been defined through its

      opposite, e.g.i. good through evil: for opposites are always

      simultaneous by nature. Some people think, also, that both are objects

      of the same science, so that the one is not even more intelligible

      than the other. One must, however, observe that it is perhaps not

      possible to define some things in any other way, e.g. the double

      without the half, and all the terms that are essentially relative: for

      in all such cases the essential being is the same as a certain

      relation to something, so that it is impossible to understand the

      one term without the other, and accordingly in the definition of the

      one the other too must be embraced. One ought to learn up all such

      points as these, and use them as occasion may seem to require.

      (2) Another is-if he has used the term defined itself. This passes

      unobserved when the actual name of the object is not used, e.g.

      supposing any one had defined the sun as a star that appears by

      day'. For in bringing in 'day' he brings in the sun. To detect

      errors of this sort, exchange the word for its definition, e.g. the

      definition of 'day' as the 'passage of the sun over the earth'.

      Clearly, whoever has said 'the passage of the sun over the earth'

      has said 'the sun', so that in bringing in the 'day' he has brought in

      the sun.

      (3) Again, see if he has defined one coordinate member of a division

      by another, e.g. 'an odd number' as 'that which is greater by one than

      an even number'. For the co-ordinate members of a division that are

      derived from the same genus are simultaneous by nature and 'odd' and

      'even' are such terms: for both are differentiae of number.

      Likewise also, see if he has defined a superior through a

      subordinate term, e.g. 'An "even number" is "a number divisible into

      halves"', or '"the good" is a "state of virtue" '. For 'half' is

      derived from 'two', and 'two' is an even number: virtue also is a kind

      of good, so that the latter terms are subordinate to the former.

      Moreover, in using the subordinate term one is bound to use the

      other as well: for whoever employs the term 'virtue' employs the

      term 'good', seeing that virtue is a certain kind of good: likewise,

      also, whoever employs the term 'half' employs the term 'even', for

      to be 'divided in half' means to be divided into two, and two is even.

      5

      Generally speaking, then, one commonplace rule relates to the

      failure to frame the expression by means of terms that are prior and

      more intelligible: and of this the subdivisions are those specified

      above. A second is, see whether, though the object is in a genus, it

      has not been placed in a genus. This sort of error is always found

      where the essence of the object does not stand first in the

      expression, e.g. the definition of 'body' as 'that which has three

      dimensions', or the definition of 'man', supposing any one to give it,

      as 'that which knows how to count': for it is not stated what it is

      that has three dimensions, or what it is that knows how to count:

      whereas the genus is meant to indicate just this, and is submitted

      first of the terms in the definition.

      Moreover, see if, while the term to be defined is used in relation

      to many things, he has failed to render it in relation to all of them;

      as (e.g.) if he define 'grammar' as the 'knowledge how to write from

      dictation': for he ought also to say that it is a knowledge how to

      read as well. For in rendering it as 'knowledge of writing' has no

      more defined it than by rendering it as 'knowledge of reading':

      neither in fact has succeeded, but only he who mentions both these

      things, since it is impossible that there should be more than one

      definition of the same thing. It is only, however, in some cases

      that what has been said corresponds to the actual state of things:

      in some it does not, e.g. all those terms which are not used

      essentially in relation to both things: as medicine is said to deal

      with the production of disease and health; for it is said

      essentially to do the
    latter, but the former only by accident: for

      it is absolutely alien to medicine to produce disease. Here, then, the

      man who renders medicine as relative to both of these things has not

      defined it any better than he who mentions the one only. In fact he

      has done it perhaps worse, for any one else besides the doctor is

      capable of producing disease.

      Moreover, in a case where the term to be defined is used in relation

      to several things, see if he has rendered it as relative to the

      worse rather than to the better; for every form of knowledge and

      potentiality is generally thought to be relative to the best.

      Again, if the thing in question be not placed in its own proper

      genus, one must examine it according to the elementary rules in regard

      to genera, as has been said before.'

      Moreover, see if he uses language which transgresses the genera of

      the things he defines, defining, e.g. justice as a 'state that

      produces equality' or 'distributes what is equal': for by defining

      it so he passes outside the sphere of virtue, and so by leaving out

      the genus of justice he fails to express its essence: for the

      essence of a thing must in each case bring in its genus. It is the

      same thing if the object be not put into its nearest genus; for the

      man who puts it into the nearest one has stated all the higher genera,

      seeing that all the higher genera are predicated of the lower. Either,

      then, it ought to be put into its nearest genus, or else to the higher

      genus all the differentiae ought to be appended whereby the nearest

      genus is defined. For then he would not have left out anything: but

      would merely have mentioned the subordinate genus by an expression

      instead of by name. On the other hand, he who mentions merely the

      higher genus by itself, does not state the subordinate genus as

      well: in saying 'plant' a man does not specify 'a tree'.

      6

      Again, in regard to the differentiae, we must examine in like manner

      whether the differentiae, too, that he has stated be those of the

      genus. For if a man has not defined the object by the differentiae

      peculiar to it, or has mentioned something such as is utterly

      incapable of being a differentia of anything, e.g. 'animal' or

      'substance', clearly he has not defined it at all: for the aforesaid

      terms do not differentiate anything at all. Further, we must see

      whether the differentia stated possesses anything that is

      co-ordinate with it in a division; for, if not, clearly the one stated

      could not be a differentia of the genus. For a genus is always divided

      by differentiae that are co-ordinate members of a division, as, for

      instance, by the terms 'walking', 'flying', 'aquatic', and 'biped'. Or

      see if, though the contrasted differentia exists, it yet is not true

      of the genus, for then, clearly, neither of them could be a

      differentia of the genus; for differentiae that are co-ordinates in

      a division with the differentia of a thing are all true of the genus

      to which the thing belongs. Likewise, also, see if, though it be true,

      yet the addition of it to the genus fails to make a species. For then,

      clearly, this could not be a specific differentia of the genus: for

      a specific differentia, if added to the genus, always makes a species.

      If, however, this be no true differentia, no more is the one

      adduced, seeing that it is a co-ordinate member of a division with

      this.

      Moreover, see if he divides the genus by a negation, as those do who

      define line as 'length without breadth': for this means simply that it

      has not any breadth. The genus will then be found to partake of its

      own species: for, since of everything either an affirmation or its

      negation is true, length must always either lack breadth or possess

      it, so that 'length' as well, i.e. the genus of 'line', will be either

      with or without breadth. But 'length without breadth' is the

      definition of a species, as also is 'length with breadth': for

      'without breadth' and 'with breadth' are differentiae, and the genus

      and differentia constitute the definition of the species. Hence the

      genus would admit of the definition of its species. Likewise, also, it

      will admit of the definition of the differentia, seeing that one or

      the other of the aforesaid differentiae is of necessity predicated

      of the genus. The usefulness of this principle is found in meeting

      those who assert the existence of 'Ideas': for if absolute length

      exist, how will it be predicable of the genus that it has breadth or

      that it lacks it? For one assertion or the other will have to be

      true of 'length' universally, if it is to be true of the genus at all:

      and this is contrary to the fact: for there exist both lengths which

      have, and lengths which have not, breadth. Hence the only people

      against whom the rule can be employed are those who assert that a

      genus is always numerically one; and this is what is done by those who

      assert the real existence of the 'Ideas'; for they allege that

      absolute length and absolute animal are the genus.

      It may be that in some cases the definer is obliged to employ a

      negation as well, e.g. in defining privations. For 'blind' means a

      thing which cannot see when its nature is to see. There is no

      difference between dividing the genus by a negation, and dividing it

      by such an affirmation as is bound to have a negation as its

      co-ordinate in a division, e.g. supposing he had defined something

      as 'length possessed of breadth'; for co-ordinate in the division with

      that which is possessed of breadth is that which possesses no

      breadth and that only, so that again the genus is divided by a

      negation.

      Again, see if he rendered the species as a differentia, as do

      those who define 'contumely' as 'insolence accompanied by jeering';

      for jeering is a kind of insolence, i.e. it is a species and not a

      differentia.

      Moreover, see if he has stated the genus as the differentia, e.g.

      'Virtue is a good or noble state: for 'good' is the genus of 'virtue'.

      Or possibly 'good' here is not the genus but the differentia, on the

      principle that the same thing cannot be in two genera of which neither

      contains the other: for 'good' does not include 'state', nor vice

      versa: for not every state is good nor every good a 'state'. Both,

      then, could not be genera, and consequently, if 'state' is the genus

      of virtue, clearly 'good' cannot be its genus: it must rather be the

      differentia'. Moreover, 'a state' indicates the essence of virtue,

      whereas 'good' indicates not the essence but a quality: and to

      indicate a quality is generally held to be the function of the

      differentia. See, further, whether the differentia rendered

      indicates an individual rather than a quality: for the general view is

      that the differentia always expresses a quality.

      Look and see, further, whether the differentia belongs only by

      accident to the object defined. For the differentia is never an

      accidental attribute, any more than the genus is: for the

      differentia of a thing cannot both belong and not belong to it.

      Moreover, if either
    the differentia or the species, or any of the

      things which are under the species, is predicable of the genus, then

      he could not have defined the term. For none of the aforesaid can

      possibly be predicated of the genus, seeing that the genus is the term

      with the widest range of all. Again, see if the genus be predicated of

      the differentia; for the general view is that the genus is predicated,

      not of the differentia, but of the objects of which the differentia is

      predicated. Animal (e.g.) is predicated of 'man' or 'ox' or other

      walking animals, not of the actual differentia itself which we

      predicate of the species. For if 'animal' is to be predicated of

      each of its differentiae, then 'animal' would be predicated of the

      species several times over; for the differentiae are predicates of the

      species. Moreover, the differentiae will be all either species or

      individuals, if they are animals; for every animal is either a species

      or an individual.

      Likewise you must inquire also if the species or any of the

      objects that come under it is predicated of the differentia: for

      this is impossible, seeing that the differentia is a term with a wider

      range than the various species. Moreover, if any of the species be

      predicated of it, the result will be that the differentia is a

      species: if, for instance, 'man' be predicated, the differentia is

      clearly the human race. Again, see if the differentia fails to be

      prior to the species: for the differentia ought to be posterior to the

      genus, but prior to the species.

      Look and see also if the differentia mentioned belongs to a

      different genus, neither contained in nor containing the genus in

      question. For the general view is that the same differentia cannot

      be used of two non-subaltern genera. Else the result will be that

      the same species as well will be in two non-subaltern genera: for each

      of the differentiae imports its own genus, e.g. 'walking' and

      'biped' import with them the genus 'animal'. If, then, each of the

      genera as well is true of that of which the differentia is true, it

     
    Previous Page Next Page
© The Read Online Free 2022~2025