The Read Online Free
  • Latest Novel
  • Hot Novel
  • Completed Novel
  • Popular Novel
  • Author List
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Young Adult
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Various Works

    Previous Page Next Page

      counter-proof that it is not true, far more likely is he to be thought

      ill-tempered-although even counter-proof is not enough: for we often

      hear arguments that are contrary to common opinions, whose solution is

      yet difficult, e.g. the argument of Zeno that it is impossible to move

      or to traverse the stadium;-but still, this is no reason for

      omitting to assert the opposites of these views. If, then, a man

      refuses to admit the proposition without having either a negative

      instance or some counter-argument to bring against it, clearly he is

      ill-tempered: for ill-temper in argument consists in answering in ways

      other than the above, so as to wreck the reasoning.

      9

      Before maintaining either a thesis or a definition the answerer

      should try his hand at attacking it by himself; for clearly his

      business is to oppose those positions from which questioners

      demolish what he has laid down.

      He should beware of maintaining a hypothesis that is generally

      rejected: and this it may be in two ways: for it may be one which

      results in absurd statements, e.g. suppose any one were to say that

      everything is in motion or that nothing is; and also there are all

      those which only a bad character would choose, and which are

      implicitly opposed to men's wishes, e.g. that pleasure is the good,

      and that to do injustice is better than to suffer it. For people

      then hate him, supposing him to maintain them not for the sake of

      argument but because he really thinks them.

      10

      Of all arguments that reason to a false conclusion the right

      solution is to demolish the point on which the fallacy that occurs

      depends: for the demolition of any random point is no solution, even

      though the point demolished be false. For the argument may contain

      many falsehoods, e.g. suppose some one to secure the premisses, 'He

      who sits, writes' and 'Socrates is sitting': for from these it follows

      that 'Socrates is writing'. Now we may demolish the proposition

      'Socrates is sitting', and still be no nearer a solution of the

      argument; it may be true that the point claimed is false; but it is

      not on that that fallacy of the argument depends: for supposing that

      any one should happen to be sitting and not writing, it would be

      impossible in such a case to apply the same solution. Accordingly,

      it is not this that needs to be demolished, but rather that 'He who

      sits, writes': for he who sits does not always write. He, then, who

      has demolished the point on which the fallacy depends, has given the

      solution of the argument completely. Any one who knows that it is on

      such and such a point that the argument depends, knows the solution of

      it, just as in the case of a figure falsely drawn. For it is not

      enough to object, even if the point demolished be a falsehood, but the

      reason of the fallacy should also be proved: for then it would be

      clear whether the man makes his objection with his eyes open or not.

      There are four possible ways of preventing a man from working his

      argument to a conclusion. It can be done either by demolishing the

      point on which the falsehood that comes about depends, or by stating

      an objection directed against the questioner: for often when a

      solution has not as a matter of fact been brought, yet the

      questioner is rendered thereby unable to pursue the argument any

      farther. Thirdly, one may object to the questions asked: for it may

      happen that what the questioner wants does not follow from the

      questions he has asked because he has asked them badly, whereas if

      something additional be granted the conclusion comes about. If,

      then, the questioner be unable to pursue his argument farther, the

      objection would properly be directed against the questioner; if he can

      do so, then it would be against his questions. The fourth and worst

      kind of objection is that which is directed to the time allowed for

      discussion: for some people bring objections of a kind which would

      take longer to answer than the length of the discussion in hand.

      There are then, as we said, four ways of making objections: but of

      them the first alone is a solution: the others are just hindrances and

      stumbling-blocks to prevent the conclusions.

      11

      Adverse criticism of an argument on its own merits, and of it when

      presented in the form of questions, are two different things. For

      often the failure to carry through the argument correctly in

      discussion is due to the person questioned, because he will not

      grant the steps of which a correct argument might have been made

      against his position: for it is not in the power of the one side

      only to effect properly a result that depends on both alike.

      Accordingly it sometimes becomes necessary to attack the speaker and

      not his position, when the answerer lies in wait for the points that

      are contrary to the questioner and becomes abusive as well: when

      people lose their tempers in this way, their argument becomes a

      contest, not a discussion. Moreover, since arguments of this kind

      are held not for the sake of instruction but for purposes of

      practice and examination, clearly one has to reason not only to true

      conclusions, but also to false ones, and not always through true

      premisses, but sometimes through false as well. For often, when a true

      proposition is put forward, the dialectician is compelled to

      demolish it: and then false propositions have to be formulated.

      Sometimes also when a false proposition is put forward, it has to be

      demolished by means of false propositions: for it is possible for a

      given man to believe what is not the fact more firmly than the

      truth. Accordingly, if the argument be made to depend on something

      that he holds, it will be easier to persuade or help him. He, however,

      who would rightly convert any one to a different opinion should do

      so in a dialectical and not in a contentious manner, just as a

      geometrician should reason geometrically, whether his conclusion be

      false or true: what kind of syllogisms are dialectical has already

      been said. The principle that a man who hinders the common business is

      a bad partner, clearly applies to an argument as well; for in

      arguments as well there is a common aim in view, except with mere

      contestants, for these cannot both reach the same goal; for more

      than one cannot possibly win. It makes no difference whether he

      effects this as answerer or as questioner: for both he who asks

      contentious questions is a bad dialectician, and also he who in

      answering fails to grant the obvious answer or to understand the point

      of the questioner's inquiry. What has been said, then, makes it

      clear that adverse criticism is not to be passed in a like strain upon

      the argument on its own merits, and upon the questioner: for it may

      very well be that the argument is bad, but that the questioner has

      argued with the answerer in the best possible way: for when men lose

      their tempers, it may perhaps be impossible to make one's inferences

      straight-forwardly as one would wish: we have to do as we can.

      Inasmuch as it is indeterminate whe
    n people are claiming the

      admission of contrary things, and when they are claiming what

      originally they set out to prove-for often when they are talking by

      themselves they say contrary things, and admit afterwards what they

      have previously denied; for which reason they often assent, when

      questioned, to contrary things and to what originally had to be

      proved-the argument is sure to become vitiated. The responsibility,

      however, for this rests with the answerer, because while refusing to

      grant other points, he does grant points of that kind. It is, then,

      clear that adverse criticism is not to be passed in a like manner upon

      questioners and upon their arguments.

      In itself an argument is liable to five kinds of adverse criticism:

      (1) The first is when neither the proposed conclusion nor indeed any

      conclusion at all is drawn from the questions asked, and when most, if

      not all, of the premisses on which the conclusion rests are false or

      generally rejected, when, moreover, neither any withdrawals nor

      additions nor both together can bring the conclusions about.

      (2) The second is, supposing the reasoning, though constructed

      from the premisses, and in the manner, described above, were to be

      irrelevant to the original position.

      (3) The third is, supposing certain additions would bring an

      inference about but yet these additions were to be weaker than those

      that were put as questions and less generally held than the

      conclusion.

      (4) Again, supposing certain withdrawals could effect the same:

      for sometimes people secure more premisses than are necessary, so that

      it is not through them that the inference comes about.

      (5) Moreover, suppose the premisses be less generally held and

      less credible than the conclusion, or if, though true, they require

      more trouble to prove than the proposed view.

      One must not claim that the reasoning to a proposed view shall in

      every case equally be a view generally accepted and convincing: for it

      is a direct result of the nature of things that some subjects of

      inquiry shall be easier and some harder, so that if a man brings

      people to accept his point from opinions that are as generally

      received as the case admits, he has argued his case correctly.

      Clearly, then, not even the argument itself is open to the same

      adverse criticism when taken in relation to the proposed conclusion

      and when taken by itself. For there is nothing to prevent the argument

      being open to reproach in itself, and yet commendable in relation to

      the proposed conclusion, or again, vice versa, being commendable in

      itself, and yet open to reproach in relation to the proposed

      conclusion, whenever there are many propositions both generally held

      and also true whereby it could easily be proved. It is possible also

      that an argument, even though brought to a conclusion, may sometimes

      be worse than one which is not so concluded, whenever the premisses of

      the former are silly, while its conclusion is not so; whereas the

      latter, though requiring certain additions, requires only such as

      are generally held and true, and moreover does not rest as an argument

      on these additions. With those which bring about a true conclusion

      by means of false premisses, it is not fair to find fault: for a false

      conclusion must of necessity always be reached from a false premiss,

      but a true conclusion may sometimes be drawn even from false

      premisses; as is clear from the Analytics.

      Whenever by the argument stated something is demonstrated, but

      that something is other than what is wanted and has no bearing

      whatever on the conclusion, then no inference as to the latter can

      be drawn from it: and if there appears to be, it will be a sophism,

      not a proof. A philosopheme is a demonstrative inference: an

      epichireme is a dialectical inference: a sophism is a contentious

      inference: an aporeme is an inference that reasons dialectically to

      a contradiction.

      If something were to be shown from premisses, both of which are

      views generally accepted, but not accepted with like conviction, it

      may very well be that the conclusion shown is something held more

      strongly than either. If, on the other hand, general opinion be for

      the one and neither for nor against the other, or if it be for the one

      and against the other, then, if the pro and con be alike in the case

      of the premisses, they will be alike for the conclusion also: if, on

      the other hand, the one preponderates, the conclusion too will

      follow suit.

      It is also a fault in reasoning when a man shows something through a

      long chain of steps, when he might employ fewer steps and those

      already included in his argument: suppose him to be showing (e.g.)

      that one opinion is more properly so called than another, and

      suppose him to make his postulates as follows: 'x-in-itself is more

      fully x than anything else': 'there genuinely exists an object of

      opinion in itself': therefore 'the object-of-opinion-in-itself is more

      fully an object of opinion than the particular objects of opinion'.

      Now 'a relative term is more fully itself when its correlate is more

      fully itself': and 'there exists a genuine opinion-in-itself, which

      will be "opinion" in a more accurate sense than the particular

      opinions': and it has been postulated both that 'a genuine

      opinion-in-itself exists', and that 'x-in-itself is more fully x

      than anything else': therefore 'this will be opinion in a more

      accurate sense'. Wherein lies the viciousness of the reasoning? Simply

      in that it conceals the ground on which the argument depends.

      12

      An argument is clear in one, and that the most ordinary, sense, if

      it be so brought to a conclusion as to make no further questions

      necessary: in another sense, and this is the type most usually

      advanced, when the propositions secured are such as compel the

      conclusion, and the argument is concluded through premisses that are

      themselves conclusions: moreover, it is so also if some step is

      omitted that generally is firmly accepted.

      An argument is called fallacious in four senses: (1) when it appears

      to be brought to a conclusion, and is not really so-what is called

      'contentious' reasoning: (2) when it comes to a conclusion but not

      to the conclusion proposed-which happens principally in the case of

      reductiones ad impossibile: (3) when it comes to the proposed

      conclusion but not according to the mode of inquiry appropriate to the

      case, as happens when a non-medical argument is taken to be a

      medical one, or one which is not geometrical for a geometrical

      argument, or one which is not dialectical for dialectical, whether the

      result reached be true or false: (4) if the conclusion be reached

      through false premisses: of this type the conclusion is sometimes

      false, sometimes true: for while a false conclusion is always the

      result of false premisses, a true conclusion may be drawn even from

      premisses that are not true, as was said above as well.

      Fallacy in argument is due to a mistake of the arguer rather than of

      the argument
    : yet it is not always the fault of the arguer either, but

      only when he is not aware of it: for we often accept on its merits

      in preference to many true ones an argument which demolishes some true

      proposition if it does so from premisses as far as possible

      generally accepted. For an argument of that kind does demonstrate

      other things that are true: for one of the premisses laid down ought

      never to be there at all, and this will then be demonstrated. If,

      however, a true conclusion were to be reached through premisses that

      are false and utterly childish, the argument is worse than many

      arguments that lead to a false conclusion, though an argument which

      leads to a false conclusion may also be of this type. Clearly then the

      first thing to ask in regard to the argument in itself is, 'Has it a

      conclusion?'; the second, 'Is the conclusion true or false?'; the

      third, 'Of what kind of premisses does it consist?': for if the

      latter, though false, be generally accepted, the argument is

      dialectical, whereas if, though true, they be generally rejected, it

      is bad: if they be both false and also entirely contrary to general

      opinion, clearly it is bad, either altogether or else in relation to

      the particular matter in hand.

      13

      Of the ways in which a questioner may beg the original question

      and also beg contraries the true account has been given in the

      Analytics:' but an account on the level of general opinion must be

      given now.

      People appear to beg their original question in five ways: the first

      and most obvious being if any one begs the actual point requiring to

      be shown: this is easily detected when put in so many words; but it is

      more apt to escape detection in the case of different terms, or a term

      and an expression, that mean the same thing. A second way occurs

      whenever any one begs universally something which he has to

      demonstrate in a particular case: suppose (e.g.) he were trying to

      prove that the knowledge of contraries is one and were to claim that

     
    Previous Page Next Page
© The Read Online Free 2022~2025