The Read Online Free
  • Latest Novel
  • Hot Novel
  • Completed Novel
  • Popular Novel
  • Author List
  • Romance & Love
  • Fantasy
  • Science Fiction
  • Young Adult
  • Mystery & Detective
  • Thrillers & Crime
  • Actions & Adventure
  • History & Fiction
  • Horror
  • Western
  • Humor

    Various Works

    Previous Page Next Page

      then, the character between these two extremes- that of a man who is

      not eminently good and just, yet whose misfortune is brought about not

      by vice or depravity, but by some error or frailty. He must be one who

      is highly renowned and prosperous- a personage like Oedipus, Thyestes,

      or other illustrious men of such families.

      A well-constructed plot should, therefore, be single in its issue,

      rather than double as some maintain. The change of fortune should be

      not from bad to good, but, reversely, from good to bad. It should come

      about as the result not of vice, but of some great error or frailty,

      in a character either such as we have described, or better rather than

      worse. The practice of the stage bears out our view. At first the

      poets recounted any legend that came in their way. Now, the best

      tragedies are founded on the story of a few houses- on the fortunes of

      Alcmaeon, Oedipus, Orestes, Meleager, Thyestes, Telephus, and those

      others who have done or suffered something terrible. A tragedy, then,

      to be perfect according to the rules of art should be of this

      construction. Hence they are in error who censure Euripides just

      because he follows this principle in his plays, many of which end

      unhappily. It is, as we have said, the right ending. The best proof is

      that on the stage and in dramatic competition, such plays, if well

      worked out, are the most tragic in effect; and Euripides, faulty

      though he may be in the general management of his subject, yet is felt

      to be the most tragic of the poets.

      In the second rank comes the kind of tragedy which some place first.

      Like the Odyssey, it has a double thread of plot, and also an opposite

      catastrophe for the good and for the bad. It is accounted the best

      because of the weakness of the spectators; for the poet is guided in

      what he writes by the wishes of his audience. The pleasure, however,

      thence derived is not the true tragic pleasure. It is proper rather to

      Comedy, where those who, in the piece, are the deadliest enemies- like

      Orestes and Aegisthus- quit the stage as friends at the close, and

      no one slays or is slain.

      POETICS|14

      XIV

      Fear and pity may be aroused by spectacular means; but they may also

      result from the inner structure of the piece, which is the better way,

      and indicates a superior poet. For the plot ought to be so constructed

      that, even without the aid of the eye, he who hears the tale told will

      thrill with horror and melt to pity at what takes Place. This is the

      impression we should receive from hearing the story of the Oedipus.

      But to produce this effect by the mere spectacle is a less artistic

      method, and dependent on extraneous aids. Those who employ spectacular

      means to create a sense not of the terrible but only of the monstrous,

      are strangers to the purpose of Tragedy; for we must not demand of

      Tragedy any and every kind of pleasure, but only that which is

      proper to it. And since the pleasure which the poet should afford is

      that which comes from pity and fear through imitation, it is evident

      that this quality must be impressed upon the incidents.

      Let us then determine what are the circumstances which strike us

      as terrible or pitiful.

      Actions capable of this effect must happen between persons who are

      either friends or enemies or indifferent to one another. If an enemy

      kills an enemy, there is nothing to excite pity either in the act or

      the intention- except so far as the suffering in itself is pitiful. So

      again with indifferent persons. But when the tragic incident occurs

      between those who are near or dear to one another- if, for example,

      a brother kills, or intends to kill, a brother, a son his father, a

      mother her son, a son his mother, or any other deed of the kind is

      done- these are the situations to be looked for by the poet. He may

      not indeed destroy the framework of the received legends- the fact,

      for instance, that Clytemnestra was slain by Orestes and Eriphyle by

      Alcmaeon- but he ought to show of his own, and skilfully handle the

      traditional. material. Let us explain more clearly what is meant by

      skilful handling.

      The action may be done consciously and with knowledge of the

      persons, in the manner of the older poets. It is thus too that

      Euripides makes Medea slay her children. Or, again, the deed of horror

      may be done, but done in ignorance, and the tie of kinship or

      friendship be discovered afterwards. The Oedipus of Sophocles is an

      example. Here, indeed, the incident is outside the drama proper; but

      cases occur where it falls within the action of the play: one may cite

      the Alcmaeon of Astydamas, or Telegonus in the Wounded Odysseus.

      Again, there is a third case- [to be about to act with knowledge of

      the persons and then not to act. The fourth case] is when some one

      is about to do an irreparable deed through ignorance, and makes the

      discovery before it is done. These are the only possible ways. For the

      deed must either be done or not done- and that wittingly or

      unwittingly. But of all these ways, to be about to act knowing the

      persons, and then not to act, is the worst. It is shocking without

      being tragic, for no disaster follows It is, therefore, never, or very

      rarely, found in poetry. One instance, however, is in the Antigone,

      where Haemon threatens to kill Creon. The next and better way is

      that the deed should be perpetrated. Still better, that it should be

      perpetrated in ignorance, and the discovery made afterwards. There

      is then nothing to shock us, while the discovery produces a

      startling effect. The last case is the best, as when in the

      Cresphontes Merope is about to slay her son, but, recognizing who he

      is, spares his life. So in the Iphigenia, the sister recognizes the

      brother just in time. Again in the Helle, the son recognizes the

      mother when on the point of giving her up. This, then, is why a few

      families only, as has been already observed, furnish the subjects of

      tragedy. It was not art, but happy chance, that led the poets in

      search of subjects to impress the tragic quality upon their plots.

      They are compelled, therefore, to have recourse to those houses

      whose history contains moving incidents like these.

      Enough has now been said concerning the structure of the

      incidents, and the right kind of plot.

      POETICS|15

      XV

      In respect of Character there are four things to be aimed at. First,

      and most important, it must be good. Now any speech or action that

      manifests moral purpose of any kind will be expressive of character:

      the character will be good if the purpose is good. This rule is

      relative to each class. Even a woman may be good, and also a slave;

      though the woman may be said to be an inferior being, and the slave

      quite worthless. The second thing to aim at is propriety. There is a

      type of manly valor; but valor in a woman, or unscrupulous

      cleverness is inappropriate. Thirdly, character must be true to

      life: for this is a distinct thing from goodness and propriety, as

      here described. The fourth point
    is consistency: for though the

      subject of the imitation, who suggested the type, be inconsistent,

      still he must be consistently inconsistent. As an example of

      motiveless degradation of character, we have Menelaus in the

      Orestes; of character indecorous and inappropriate, the lament of

      Odysseus in the Scylla, and the speech of Melanippe; of inconsistency,

      the Iphigenia at Aulis- for Iphigenia the suppliant in no way

      resembles her later self.

      As in the structure of the plot, so too in the portraiture of

      character, the poet should always aim either at the necessary or the

      probable. Thus a person of a given character should speak or act in

      a given way, by the rule either of necessity or of probability; just

      as this event should follow that by necessary or probable sequence. It

      is therefore evident that the unraveling of the plot, no less than the

      complication, must arise out of the plot itself, it must not be

      brought about by the Deus ex Machina- as in the Medea, or in the

      return of the Greeks in the Iliad. The Deus ex Machina should be

      employed only for events external to the drama- for antecedent or

      subsequent events, which lie beyond the range of human knowledge,

      and which require to be reported or foretold; for to the gods we

      ascribe the power of seeing all things. Within the action there must

      be nothing irrational. If the irrational cannot be excluded, it should

      be outside the scope of the tragedy. Such is the irrational element

      the Oedipus of Sophocles.

      Again, since Tragedy is an imitation of persons who are above the

      common level, the example of good portrait painters should be

      followed. They, while reproducing the distinctive form of the

      original, make a likeness which is true to life and yet more

      beautiful. So too the poet, in representing men who are irascible or

      indolent, or have other defects of character, should preserve the type

      and yet ennoble it. In this way Achilles is portrayed by Agathon and

      Homer.

      These then are rules the poet should observe. Nor should he

      neglect those appeals to the senses, which, though not among the

      essentials, are the concomitants of poetry; for here too there is much

      room for error. But of this enough has been said in our published

      treatises.

      POETICS|16

      XVI

      What Recognition is has been already explained. We will now

      enumerate its kinds.

      First, the least artistic form, which, from poverty of wit, is

      most commonly employed- recognition by signs. Of these some are

      congenital- such as 'the spear which the earth-born race bear on their

      bodies,' or the stars introduced by Carcinus in his Thyestes. Others

      are acquired after birth; and of these some are bodily marks, as

      scars; some external tokens, as necklaces, or the little ark in the

      Tyro by which the discovery is effected. Even these admit of more or

      less skilful treatment. Thus in the recognition of Odysseus by his

      scar, the discovery is made in one way by the nurse, in another by the

      swineherds. The use of tokens for the express purpose of proof- and,

      indeed, any formal proof with or without tokens- is a less artistic

      mode of recognition. A better kind is that which comes about by a turn

      of incident, as in the Bath Scene in the Odyssey.

      Next come the recognitions invented at will by the poet, and on that

      account wanting in art. For example, Orestes in the Iphigenia

      reveals the fact that he is Orestes. She, indeed, makes herself

      known by the letter; but he, by speaking himself, and saying what

      the poet, not what the plot requires. This, therefore, is nearly

      allied to the fault above mentioned- for Orestes might as well have

      brought tokens with him. Another similar instance is the 'voice of the

      shuttle' in the Tereus of Sophocles.

      The third kind depends on memory when the sight of some object

      awakens a feeling: as in the Cyprians of Dicaeogenes, where the hero

      breaks into tears on seeing the picture; or again in the Lay of

      Alcinous, where Odysseus, hearing the minstrel play the lyre,

      recalls the past and weeps; and hence the recognition.

      The fourth kind is by process of reasoning. Thus in the Choephori:

      'Some one resembling me has come: no one resembles me but Orestes:

      therefore Orestes has come.' Such too is the discovery made by

      Iphigenia in the play of Polyidus the Sophist. It was a natural

      reflection for Orestes to make, 'So I too must die at the altar like

      my sister.' So, again, in the Tydeus of Theodectes, the father says,

      'I came to find my son, and I lose my own life.' So too in the

      Phineidae: the women, on seeing the place, inferred their fate-

      'Here we are doomed to die, for here we were cast forth.' Again, there

      is a composite kind of recognition involving false inference on the

      part of one of the characters, as in the Odysseus Disguised as a

      Messenger. A said [that no one else was able to bend the bow; ...

      hence B (the disguised Odysseus) imagined that A would] recognize

      the bow which, in fact, he had not seen; and to bring about a

      recognition by this means- the expectation that A would recognize

      the bow- is false inference.

      But, of all recognitions, the best is that which arises from the

      incidents themselves, where the startling discovery is made by natural

      means. Such is that in the Oedipus of Sophocles, and in the Iphigenia;

      for it was natural that Iphigenia should wish to dispatch a letter.

      These recognitions alone dispense with the artificial aid of tokens or

      amulets. Next come the recognitions by process of reasoning.

      POETICS|17

      XVII

      In constructing the plot and working it out with the proper diction,

      the poet should place the scene, as far as possible, before his

      eyes. In this way, seeing everything with the utmost vividness, as

      if he were a spectator of the action, he will discover what is in

      keeping with it, and be most unlikely to overlook inconsistencies. The

      need of such a rule is shown by the fault found in Carcinus.

      Amphiaraus was on his way from the temple. This fact escaped the

      observation of one who did not see the situation. On the stage,

      however, the Piece failed, the audience being offended at the

      oversight.

      Again, the poet should work out his play, to the best of his

      power, with appropriate gestures; for those who feel emotion are

      most convincing through natural sympathy with the characters they

      represent; and one who is agitated storms, one who is angry rages,

      with the most lifelike reality. Hence poetry implies either a happy

      gift of nature or a strain of madness. In the one case a man can

      take the mould of any character; in the other, he is lifted out of his

      proper self.

      As for the story, whether the poet takes it ready made or constructs

      it for himself, he should first sketch its general outline, and then

      fill in the episodes and amplify in detail. The general plan may be

      illustrated by the Iphigenia. A young girl is sacrificed; she

      disappears mysteriously from the eyes of those who sacrificed her; she


      is transported to another country, where the custom is to offer up

      an strangers to the goddess. To this ministry she is appointed. Some

      time later her own brother chances to arrive. The fact that the oracle

      for some reason ordered him to go there, is outside the general plan

      of the play. The purpose, again, of his coming is outside the action

      proper. However, he comes, he is seized, and, when on the point of

      being sacrificed, reveals who he is. The mode of recognition may be

      either that of Euripides or of Polyidus, in whose play he exclaims

      very naturally: 'So it was not my sister only, but I too, who was

      doomed to be sacrificed'; and by that remark he is saved.

      After this, the names being once given, it remains to fill in the

      episodes. We must see that they are relevant to the action. In the

      case of Orestes, for example, there is the madness which led to his

      capture, and his deliverance by means of the purificatory rite. In the

      drama, the episodes are short, but it is these that give extension

      to Epic poetry. Thus the story of the Odyssey can be stated briefly. A

      certain man is absent from home for many years; he is jealously

      watched by Poseidon, and left desolate. Meanwhile his home is in a

      wretched plight- suitors are wasting his substance and plotting

      against his son. At length, tempest-tost, he himself arrives; he makes

      certain persons acquainted with him; he attacks the suitors with his

      own hand, and is himself preserved while he destroys them. This is the

      essence of the plot; the rest is episode.

      POETICS|18

      XVIII

      Every tragedy falls into two parts- Complication and Unraveling

      or Denouement. Incidents extraneous to the action are frequently

      combined with a portion of the action proper, to form the

      Complication; the rest is the Unraveling. By the Complication I mean

      all that extends from the beginning of the action to the part which

      marks the turning-point to good or bad fortune. The Unraveling is that

     
    Previous Page Next Page
© The Read Online Free 2022~2025