fact, I was so convinced that not even a stripe of colour appears from what

  would commonly be called an accident, that I was led solely from the

  occurrence of the face-stripes on this hybrid from the ass and hemionus, to

  ask Colonel Poole whether such face-stripes ever occur in the eminently

  striped Kattywar breed of horses, and was, as we have seen, answered in the

  affirmative.

  What now are we to say to these several facts? We see several very

  distinct species of the horse-genus becoming, by simple variation, striped

  on the legs like a zebra, or striped on the shoulders like an ass. In the

  horse we see this tendency strong whenever a dun tint appears--a tint which

  approaches to that of the general colouring of the other species of the

  genus. The appearance of the stripes is not accompanied by any change of

  form or by any other new character. We see this tendency to become striped

  most strongly displayed in hybrids from between several of the most

  distinct species. Now observe the case of the several breeds of pigeons:

  they are descended from a pigeon (including two or three sub-species or

  geographical races) of a bluish colour, with certain bars and other marks;

  and when any breed assumes by simple variation a bluish tint, these bars

  and other marks invariably reappear; but without any other change of form

  or character. When the oldest and truest breeds of various colours are

  crossed, we see a strong tendency for the blue tint and bars and marks to

  reappear in the mongrels. I have stated that the most probable hypothesis

  to account for the reappearance of very ancient characters, is--that there

  is a tendency in the young of each successive generation to produce the

  long-lost character, and that this tendency, from unknown causes, sometimes

  prevails. And we have just seen that in several species of the horse-genus

  the stripes are either plainer or appear more commonly in the young than in

  the old. Call the breeds of pigeons, some of which have bred true for

  centuries, species; and how exactly parallel is the case with that of the

  species of the horse-genus! For myself, I venture confidently to look back

  thousands on thousands of generations, and I see an animal striped like a

  zebra, but perhaps otherwise very differently constructed, the common

  parent of our domestic horse, whether or not it be descended from one or

  more wild stocks, of the ass, the hemionus, quagga, and zebra.

  He who believes that each equine species was independently created, will, I

  presume, assert that each species has been created with a tendency to vary,

  both under nature and under domestication, in this particular manner, so as

  often to become striped like other species of the genus; and that each has

  been created with a strong tendency, when crossed with species inhabiting

  distant quarters of the world, to produce hybrids resembling in their

  stripes, not their own parents, but other species of the genus. To admit

  this view is, as it seems to me, to reject a real for an unreal, or at

  least for an unknown, cause. It makes the works of God a mere mockery and

  deception; I would almost as soon believe with the old and ignorant

  cosmogonists, that fossil shells had never lived, but had been created in

  stone so as to mock the shells now living on the sea-shore.

  Summary. -- Our ignorance of the laws of variation is profound. Not in one

  case out of a hundred can we pretend to assign any reason why this or that

  part differs, more or less, from the same part in the parents. But

  whenever we have the means of instituting a comparison, the same laws

  appear to have acted in producing the lesser differences between varieties

  of the same species, and the greater differences between species of the

  same genus. The external conditions of life, as climate and food, &c.,

  seem to have induced some slight modifications. Habit in producing

  constitutional differences, and use in strengthening, and disuse in

  weakening and diminishing organs, seem to have been more potent in their

  effects. Homologous parts tend to vary in the same way, and homologous

  parts tend to cohere. Modifications in hard parts and in external parts

  sometimes affect softer and internal parts. When one part is largely

  developed, perhaps it tends to draw nourishment from the adjoining parts;

  and every part of the structure which can be saved without detriment to the

  individual, will be saved. Changes of structure at an early age will

  generally affect parts subsequently developed; and there are very many

  other correlations of growth, the nature of which we are utterly unable to

  understand. Multiple parts are variable in number and in structure,

  perhaps arising from such parts not having been closely specialised to any

  particular function, so that their modifications have not been closely

  checked by natural selection. It is probably from this same cause that

  organic beings low in the scale of nature are more variable than those

  which have their whole organisation more specialised, and are higher in the

  scale. Rudimentary organs, from being useless, will be disregarded by

  natural selection, and hence probably are variable. Specific

  characters--that is, the characters which have come to differ since the

  several species of the same genus branched off from a common parent--are

  more variable than generic characters, or those which have long been

  inherited, and have not differed within this same period. In these remarks

  we have referred to special parts or organs being still variable, because

  they have recently varied and thus come to differ; but we have also seen in

  the second Chapter that the same principle applies to the whole individual;

  for in a district where many species of any genus are found--that is, where

  there has been much former variation and differentiation, or where the

  manufactory of new specific forms has been actively at work--there, on an

  average, we now find most varieties or incipient species. Secondary sexual

  characters are highly variable, and such characters differ much in the

  species of the same group. Variability in the same parts of the

  organisation has generally been taken advantage of in giving secondary

  sexual differences to the sexes of the same species, and specific

  differences to the several species of the same genus. Any part or organ

  developed to an extraordinary size or in an extraordinary manner, in

  comparison with the same part or organ in the allied species, must have

  gone through an extraordinary amount of modification since the genus arose;

  and thus we can understand why it should often still be variable in a much

  higher degree than other parts; for variation is a long-continued and slow

  process, and natural selection will in such cases not as yet have had time

  to overcome the tendency to further variability and to reversion to a less

  modified state. But when a species with any extraordinarily-developed

  organ has become the parent of many modified descendants--which on my view

  must be a very slow process, requiring a long lapse of time--in this case,

  natural selection may readily have succeeded in giving a fixed character to


  the organ, in however extraordinary a manner it may be developed. Species

  inheriting nearly the same constitution from a common parent and exposed to

  similar influences will naturally tend to present analogous variations, and

  these same species may occasionally revert to some of the characters of

  their ancient progenitors. Although new and important modifications may

  not arise from reversion and analogous variation, such modifications will

  add to the beautiful and harmonious diversity of nature.

  Whatever the cause may be of each slight difference in the offspring from

  their parents--and a cause for each must exist--it is the steady

  accumulation, through natural selection, of such differences, when

  beneficial to the individual, that gives rise to all the more important

  modifications of structure, by which the innumerable beings on the face of

  this earth are enabled to struggle with each other, and the best adapted to

  survive.

  Chapter VI

  Difficulties on Theory

  Difficulties on the theory of descent with modification -- Transitions --

  Absence or rarity of transitional varieties -- Transitions in habits of

  life -- Diversified habits in the same species -- Species with habits

  widely different from those of their allies -- Organs of extreme perfection

  -- Means of transition -- Cases of difficulty -- Natura non facit saltum --

  Organs of small importance -- Organs not in all cases absolutely perfect --

  The law of Unity of Type and of the Conditions of Existence embraced by the

  theory of Natural Selection.

  Long before having arrived at this part of my work, a crowd of difficulties

  will have occurred to the reader. Some of them are so grave that to this

  day I can never reflect on them without being staggered; but, to the best

  of my judgment, the greater number are only apparent, and those that are

  real are not, I think, fatal to my theory.

  These difficulties and objections may be classed under the following

  heads:- Firstly, why, if species have descended from other species by

  insensibly fine gradations, do we not everywhere see innumerable

  transitional forms? Why is not all nature in confusion instead of the

  species being, as we see them, well defined?

  Secondly, is it possible that an animal having, for instance, the structure

  and habits of a bat, could have been formed by the modification of some

  animal with wholly different habits? Can we believe that natural selection

  could produce, on the one hand, organs of trifling importance, such as the

  tail of a giraffe, which serves as a fly-flapper, and, on the other hand,

  organs of such wonderful structure, as the eye, of which we hardly as yet

  fully understand the inimitable perfection?

  Thirdly, can instincts be acquired and modified through natural selection?

  What shall we say to so marvellous an instinct as that which leads the bee

  to make cells, which have practically anticipated the discoveries of

  profound mathematicians?

  Fourthly, how can we account for species, when crossed, being sterile and

  producing sterile offspring, whereas, when varieties are crossed, their

  fertility is unimpaired?

  The two first heads shall be here discussed--Instinct and Hybridism in

  separate chapters.

  On the absence or rarity of transitional varieties. -- As natural selection

  acts solely by the preservation of profitable modifications, each new form

  will tend in a fully-stocked country to take the place of, and finally to

  exterminate, its own less improved parent or other less-favoured forms with

  which it comes into competition. Thus extinction and natural selection

  will, as we have seen, go hand in hand. Hence, if we look at each species

  as descended from some other unknown form, both the parent and all the

  transitional varieties will generally have been exterminated by the very

  process of formation and perfection of the new form.

  But, as by this theory innumerable transitional forms must have existed,

  why do we not find them embedded in countless numbers in the crust of the

  earth? It will be much more convenient to discuss this question in the

  chapter on the Imperfection of the geological record; and I will here only

  state that I believe the answer mainly lies in the record being

  incomparably less perfect than is generally supposed; the imperfection of

  the record being chiefly due to organic beings not inhabiting profound

  depths of the sea, and to their remains being embedded and preserved to a

  future age only in masses of sediment sufficiently thick and extensive to

  withstand an enormous amount of future degradation; and such fossiliferous

  masses can be accumulated only where much sediment is deposited on the

  shallow bed of the sea, whilst it slowly subsides. These contingencies

  will concur only rarely, and after enormously long intervals. Whilst the

  bed of the sea is stationary or is rising, or when very little sediment is

  being deposited, there will be blanks in our geological history. The crust

  of the earth is a vast museum; but the natural collections have been made

  only at intervals of time immensely remote.

  But it may be urged that when several closely-allied species inhabit the

  same territory we surely ought to find at the present time many

  transitional forms. Let us take a simple case: in travelling from north

  to south over a continent, we generally meet at successive intervals with

  closely allied or representative species, evidently filling nearly the same

  place in the natural economy of the land. These representative species

  often meet and interlock; and as the one becomes rarer and rarer, the other

  becomes more and more frequent, till the one replaces the other. But if we

  compare these species where they intermingle, they are generally as

  absolutely distinct from each other in every detail of structure as are

  specimens taken from the metropolis inhabited by each. By my theory these

  allied species have descended from a common parent; and during the process

  of modification, each has become adapted to the conditions of life of its

  own region, and has supplanted and exterminated its original parent and all

  the transitional varieties between its past and present states. Hence we

  ought not to expect at the present time to meet with numerous transitional

  varieties in each region, though they must have existed there, and may be

  embedded there in a fossil condition. But in the intermediate region,

  having intermediate conditions of life, why do we not now find

  closely-linking intermediate varieties? This difficulty for a long time

  quite confounded me. But I think it can be in large part explained.

  In the first place we should be extremely cautious in inferring, because an

  area is now continuous, that it has been continuous during a long period.

  Geology would lead us to believe that almost every continent has been

  broken up into islands even during the later tertiary periods; and in such

  islands distinct species might have been separately formed without the

  possibility of intermediate varieties existing in the intermediate zones.

  By changes in the f
orm of the land and of climate, marine areas now

  continuous must often have existed within recent times in a far less

  continuous and uniform condition than at present. But I will pass over

  this way of escaping from the difficulty; for I believe that many perfectly

  defined species have been formed on strictly continuous areas; though I do

  not doubt that the formerly broken condition of areas now continuous has

  played an important part in the formation of new species, more especially

  with freely-crossing and wandering animals.

  In looking at species as they are now distributed over a wide area, we

  generally find them tolerably numerous over a large territory, then

  becoming somewhat abruptly rarer and rarer on the confines, and finally

  disappearing. Hence the neutral territory between two representative

  species is generally narrow in comparison with the territory proper to

  each. We see the same fact in ascending mountains, and sometimes it is

  quite remarkable how abruptly, as Alph. De Candolle has observed, a common

  alpine species disappears. The same fact has been noticed by Forbes in

  sounding the depths of the sea with the dredge. To those who look at

  climate and the physical conditions of life as the all-important elements

  of distribution, these facts ought to cause surprise, as climate and height

  or depth graduate away insensibly. But when we bear in mind that almost

  every species, even in its metropolis, would increase immensely in numbers,

  were it not for other competing species; that nearly all either prey on or

  serve as prey for others; in short, that each organic being is either

  directly or indirectly related in the most important manner to other

  organic beings, we must see that the range of the inhabitants of any

  country by no means exclusively depends on insensibly changing physical

  conditions, but in large part on the presence of other species, on which it

  depends, or by which it is destroyed, or with which it comes into

  competition; and as these species are already defined objects (however they

  may have become so), not blending one into another by insensible

  gradations, the range of any one species, depending as it does on the range

  of others, will tend to be sharply defined. Moreover, each species on the

  confines of its range, where it exists in lessened numbers, will, during

  fluctuations in the number of its enemies or of its prey, or in the

  seasons, be extremely liable to utter extermination; and thus its

  geographical range will come to be still more sharply defined.

  If I am right in believing that allied or representative species, when

  inhabiting a continuous area, are generally so distributed that each has a

  wide range, with a comparatively narrow neutral territory between them, in

  which they become rather suddenly rarer and rarer; then, as varieties do

  not essentially differ from species, the same rule will probably apply to

  both; and if we in imagination adapt a varying species to a very large

  area, we shall have to adapt two varieties to two large areas, and a third

  variety to a narrow intermediate zone. The intermediate variety,

  consequently, will exist in lesser numbers from inhabiting a narrow and

  lesser area; and practically, as far as I can make out, this rule holds

  good with varieties in a state of nature. I have met with striking

  instances of the rule in the case of varieties intermediate between

  well-marked varieties in the genus Balanus. And it would appear from

  information given me by Mr. Watson, Dr. Asa Gray, and Mr. Wollaston, that

  generally when varieties intermediate between two other forms occur, they

  are much rarer numerically than the forms which they connect. Now, if we

  may trust these facts and inferences, and therefore conclude that varieties

  linking two other varieties together have generally existed in lesser

  numbers than the forms which they connect, then, I think, we can understand