The semantic confusion in the discussion of the problems concerned is due to an inaccurate use of terms on the part of many economists. An economist investigates whether a measure a can bring about the result p for the attainment of which it is recommended, and finds that a does not result in p but in g, an effect which even the supporters of the measure a consider undesirable. If this economist states the outcome of his investigation by saying that a is a bad measure, he does not pronounce a judgment of value. He merely says that from the point of view of those aiming at the goal p, the measure a is inappropriate. In this sense the free-trade economists attacked protection. They demonstrated that protection does not, as its champions believe, increase but, on the contrary, decreases the total amount of products, and is therefore bad from the point of view of those who prefer an ampler supply of products to a smaller. It is in this sense that economists criticize policies from the point of view of the ends aimed at. If an economist calls minimum wage rates a bad policy, what he means is that its effects are contrary to the purpose of those who recommend their application.

  From the same point of view praxeology and economics look upon the fundamental principle of human existence and social evolution, viz., that cooperation under the social division of labor is a more efficient way of acting than is the autarkic isolation of individuals. Praxeology and economics do not say that men should peacefully cooperate within the frame of societal bonds; they merely say that men must act this way if they want to make their actions more successful than otherwise. Compliance with the moral rules which the establishment, preservation, and intensification of social cooperation require is not seen as a sacrifice made to a mythical entity, but as the recourse to the most efficient methods of action, as a price expended for the attainment of more highly valued returns.

  It is against this substitution of an autonomous, rationalistic and voluntaristic ethics for the heteronomous doctrines both of intuitionism and of revealed commandments that the united forces of all antiliberal schools and dogmatisms direct the most furious attacks They all blame the utilitarian philosophy for the pitiless austerity of its description and analysis of human nature and of the ultimate springs of human action. It is not necessary to add anything more to the refutation of these criticisms which every page of this book provides. Only one point should be mentioned again, because on the one hand it is the acme of the doctrine of all contemporary pied pipers and on the other hand it offers to the average intellectual a welcome excuse to shun the painstaking discipline of economic studies.

  Economics, it is said, in its rationalistic prepossessions assumes that men aim only or first of all at material well-being. But in reality men prefer irrational objectives to rational ones. They are guided more by the urge to realize myths and ideals than by the urge to enjoy a higher standard of living.

  What economics has to answer is this:

  1. Economics does not assume or postulate that men aim only or first of all at what is called material well-being. Economics, as a branch of the more general theory of human action, deals with all human action, i.e., with man's purposive aiming at the attainment of ends chosen, whatever these ends may be. To apply the concept rational or irrational to the ultimate ends chosen is nonsensical. We may call irrational the ultimate given, viz., those things that our thinking can neither analyze nor reduce to other ultimately given things. Then every ultimate end chosen by any man is irrational. It is neither more nor less rational to aim at riches like Croesus than to aim at poverty like a Buddhist monk.

  2. What these critics have in mind when employing the term rational ends is the desire for material well-being and a higher standard of living. It is a question of fact whether or not their statement is true that men in general and our contemporaries especially are driven more by the wish to realize myths and dreams than by the wish to improve their material well-being. Although no intelligent being could fail to give the correct answer, we may disregard the issue. For economics does not say anything either in favor of or against myths. It is perfectly neutral with regard to the labor-union doctrine, the credit-expansion doctrine and all such doctrines as far as these may present themselves as myths and are supported as myths by their partisans. It deals with these doctrines only as far as they are considered doctrines about the means fit for the attainment of definite ends. Economics does not say labor unionism is a bad myth. It merely says it is an inappropriate means of raising wage rates for all those eager to earn wages. It leaves it to every man to decide whether the realization of the labor-union myth is more important than the avoidance of the inevitable consequences of labor-union policies.

  In this sense we may say that economics is apolitical or nonpolitical, although it is the foundation of politics and of every kind of political action. We may furthermore say that it is perfectly neutral with regard to all judgments of value, as it refers always to means and never to the choice of ultimate ends.

  3. Economic Cognition and Human Action

  Man's freedom to choose and to act is restricted in a threefold way. There are first the physical laws to whose unfeeling absoluteness man must adjust his conduct if he wants to live. There are second the individual's innate constitutional characteristics and dispositions and the operation of environmental factors; we know that they influence both the choice of the ends and that of the means, although our cognizance of the mode of their operation is rather vague. There is finally the regularity of phenomena with regard to the interconnectedness of means and ends, viz., the praxeological law as distinct from the physical and the physiological law.

  The elucidation and the categorial and formal examination of this third class of the laws of the universe is the subject matter of praxeology and its hitherto best-developed branch, economics. The body of economic knowledge is an essential element in the structure of human civilization; it is the foundation upon which modern industrialism and all the moral, intellectual, technological, and therapeutical achievements of the last centuries have been built. It rests with men whether they will make the proper use of the rich treasure with which this knowledge provides them or whether they will leave it unused. But if they fail to take the best advantage of it and disregard its teachings and warnings, they will not annul economics; they will stamp out society and the human race.

  INDEX

  A | B | C | D | E

  F | G | H | I | J

  K | L | M | N | O

  P | Q | R | S | T

  U | V | W | Y

  Prepared in 1954 by Vern Crawford for the 1949 first

  edition of Human Action. This index is more complete

  than the one included in the book itself.

  A

  Ability-to-pay principle

  in fixing wage rates, 811–812

  in taxation, 731–732

  Abnormality, 95 see also, Irrationality

  Absolute, 28, 70, 72

  Abstinence, reward of, 842n

  Abundance, 234–237 see also, Saving; Scarcity

  Acceleration principle, 581–583

  Accounting

  capital, 231, 260–264, 468, 488, 511, 517

  cost, 336–347

  method of, 214, 301

  Accounts, foreign exchange equalization, 458–459, 781

  Accumulation, capital, 465, 487–490, 511–514, 518n, 840–847

  Acting man, ch. 1, pp. 11–29

  Action, human, Part 1, pp. 11–142

  analysis of, ch. 4, pp. 92–98

  as an ultimate given, 17–18

  backwardness of science of, 664n

  calculative, 199–200

  categories of, 64, 196

  causality and, 22–23

  changing features of, 18, 46–47, 223

  differs from psychology, 12

  economic calculation and, 232

  economic cognition and, 881

  emotional, 16

  ends and means of, 70, 92–94, 201–202, 208, 476

  epistemological problems of, 4–7; ch. 2, pp. 30–71


  exchange and, 97–98

  goals of, 15, 315

  history and, 59

  individual and, 45–47, 403, 719–725

  influenced by past action, 502–510

  in passing of time, ch. 18, pp. 476–520

  insecurity and, 847–849

  marginal utility and, 119–124, 632

  meaning of, 11, 26, 28, 42, 59, 92

  monetary calculation as tool of, ch. 13, pp. 230–232

  originary interest and, 524

  practice of, 7–10

  prerequisites of, 13–16

  on happiness, 14–15

  on instincts and impulses, 15–16

  purposeful, 11–13

  requisite of, 22–23, 480–487

  righteousness of, 719–725

  routine and, 46–47

  science and, 6, 21, 30, 51, 57

  selfish, 243, 674

  social cooperation and, see, Cooperation, social

  temporal relation between, 102–104, 490

  theory of, 4–7

  thinking and, 24, 177, 584n

  tool of, ch. 13, pp. 230–232

  uncertainty and, ch. 6, pp. 105–118, 249

  value judgment and, 17, 491

  within framework of society, ch. 7, pp. 119–142; Part 2, pp. 143–200 see also, Praxeology; Rationalism;

  Understanding; Valuation;

  Want-satisfaction; World view

  Adams, Thomas Sewall, 523n, 734n

  Adjustment, period of, 648–650

  Advertising, 316–319, 378n see also, Propaganda

  Age of Reason, 69

  Aggression and destruction, 169–173

  Agreements

  barter, 796–799

  bilateral exchange, 794–796

  clearing, 472, 796

  Agriculture

  monopoly and, 367

  New Deal and, 236, 384

  subsidies and, 365, 600n, 656

  Alter ego, 23–26

  American Institutionalism, 4, 755

  Amonn, Alfred Otto, 631n

  Amortization of taxes, 640

  Analogies, 114

  Anarchism, 148–149, 191, 240, 256, 248n, 579–580

  Ancestors, 3, 36, 145

  Anderson, Benjamin McAlester, 406n

  Animals

  reaction to purposeful action, 11–13, 16

  use of, 624

  Anteriority and consequence, 99

  Anthropomorphism, 69

  Antimonopoly party, 383

  Apologists, 48 see also, Propaganda

  A posteriori theory, 31, 41

  Appraisement and valuation, 328–332

  Apriorism

  methodological, 35, 65

  of praxeology, 32–36, 64–65, 407

  reality and, 38–41

  reasoning of, 38, 318

  science of, 48

  Aquinas, Thomas, 723

  Arbitration, 770

  Aristotle, 204, 845n

  Artists, 241n see also, Genius

  Asceticism, 28–29, 87, 178–180

  Assisi, St. Francis D', 156

  Association

  human process of, 147n

  Ricardian law of, 158–163, 168, 174

  Atheist, 147n

  Atomic bomb, 828

  Austria

  economists of, 4, 120, 492–493

  Post Office Savings Service of, 442

  Autarky, 163, 267n, 314, 322, 743, 824–826

  Authority, importance of, 284, 321

  Autistic economy, 195–196, 244–245

  Autocracy, 647, 686

  Automatic, economic meaning of, 725

  Averages, Computation of, 223

  B

  Backwardness, technological, 504–505

  Bailey, Samuel, 220

  Baker, John Randall, 496n

  Balance of payments, 447–449, 453–455

  Balance sheets, 213

  Balkania, 797

  Ballistics, 77

  Banking School, 436–437, 441

  Banknotes, 441–445

  Banks and banking

  booms and, 559

  British, 439

  cartels of, 444

  central, 457, 462

  currency expansion and, 789n

  European, 442

  Federal Reserve Act of 1913, 566

  fiduciary media and, 431

  free, 440, 441–445

  international, 473

  interventionism and, 437, 444

  liberalism and, 440–141

  loans, 568

  private, 462

  Swiss, 462, 463 see also, Credit expansion; Cycle theory; Malinvestment; Money; Trade

  “Barbarous relics,” 468

  Barone, Enrico, 697

  Barter

  agreements, 796–799

  fiction, of value and prices, 202–206

  Bastiat, Frédéric, 147n, 827

  Beard, Charles and Mary, 625n

  Behaviorism

  animal versus man, 16

  conscious versus unconscious, 11

  criticism of, 7

  purposeful, 26–27

  Bentham, Jeremy, 174, 192–193, 670, 827, 830

  Berdyaew, Nicolas, 671n

  Bergmann, Ernst, 204n

  Bergson, Henri, 33n, 49, 100n

  Bernard, Claude, 28n

  Bernoulli, Daniel

  doctrine de mensura sortis, 125–126

  Betting, 115–116

  Beveridge, William Henry, 764

  Bias, 48, 686 see also, Valuation

  Bilateral exchange agreements, 794–796

  Bimetallism, 468–469, 775–776

  Birth control, 663

  Bismarck, Otto, 363, 364

  Bodin, Jean, 232, 817

  Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen, 121, 202n, 311, 477, 478, 479, 484–486, 523, 524–525

  Bonald, Louis, 860

  Bonaparte, Louis Napoleon, 509, 662

  Bonar, James, 664n

  Bondage, 197, 624–630, 817, 835

  Bonds

  contractual and hegemonic, 196–199, 280, 281, 497, 461, 841

  government, 226

  Bookkeeping, 231, 301

  Booms

  characteristics of, 550–562

  crack up, 424, 433

  economic progress and, 573, 576–578

  end of, 783

  generation of, 789n

  industry and, 557

  investments and, 574 see also, Credit expansion; Cycle theory; Depressions

  Bourgeoisie, 9, 74, 78, 81, 268, 605

  Brentano, Lujo, 618

  Bretton Woods Conference, 475

  Bribery, 273

  British, see, Great Britain

  Brüning, Heinrich, 855

  Brunner, Emil, 671n

  Buddhism, 28

  Bureaucratic management, 300–307

  Burke, Edmund, 860

  Business

  calculation, 301

  fluctuations, 583

  forecasting, 649, 866–868

  good will and, 3 76

  New Deal plan to control, 815

  outlays, 242n

  production and, 489

  propaganda, 316–319

  risk-taking and, 106, 108, 112, 115, 805–807

  socialist control of, 257 see also, Entrepreneurs; Interventionism

  C

  Caesarism, 182n

  Cairnes, John Elliott, 204, 627n

  Calculation

  business, 301

  economic, see, Economic calculation in Soviet Russia and Nazi Germany, 698–699

  lack of precision in, 225n

  monetary, ch. 13, pp. 230–232

  valuation and, 97; ch. 11, pp. 201–212 see also, Accounting; Mathematics; Measurement

  Carman, Edwin, 532n

  Capacity, unused, 391, 576–578

  Capital

  accounting, 231, 260–264, 468, 488, 511, 617

  accumulation of, 465, 487–490, 511–514, 518n, 840–847

  circulating, 557
r />
  consumption, 261, 511–514, 846

  convertibility of, 499–502, 505, 510

  fixed, 557

  flight, 515

  foreign, 493–495, 497–499

  goods, 263, 292, 293, 487–490, 493, 499–502, 505, 510

  income and, 260–261, 482

  investment, 342, 369, 378, 499

  labor and, 637

  maintenance, 260–264, 511–514, 844–845

  marginal productivity of, 293, 632

  market, 543

  praxeology and, 482, 512

  stock exchange and, 514–517