the simple exchange economy is the separation of labour and capital, that is, the existence

  of a labour force without its own sufficient capital and therefore without a choice as to

  whether to put its labour in the market or not" Democratic Theory, 146.

  41 This and other interesting points appear in an unpublished paper by Frances Piven and

  Barbara Ehrenreich, "Toward a Just and Adequate Welfare State."

  42 New York Times, Aug. 21, 1983.

  43 Robert Kuttner, "A Myth for Modern Times," Boston Observer (Oct. 1984).

  44 U.S. District Judge Miles Lord, quoted in the Minneapolis Star and Tribune, May 18, 1984.

  Those who might cite this as an example of true justice in our courts should know that

  Judge Lord, after making these statements, was put under investigation by a panel of his

  col eagues and later resigned.

  45 Professor Andrew Schotter, of New York University, author of Free Market Economics,

  quoted in the New York Times, Nov. 7, 1984.

  46 Alexander Cockburn, "Getting Opium to the Masses: The Political Economy of Addiction,"

  The Nation, Oct. 30, 1989.

  47 An Associated Press dispatch of Oct. 24, 1981:

  Al pans of the world's oceans are pol uted and face the possibility of irreversible damage

  within 25 years according to scientists at an ocean pol ution conference here.

  John Vandermeulen of the Bedford Institute of Oceanography, summarizing the conclusions

  of the weeklong conference, said, "There exists no longer any virgin, contaminant-free nook

  or corner in the marine environment, including the high Arctic and the sediments of the

  deep.

  48 Cosmopolitan Magazine, Jan. 1907.

  49 Quoted by Howard Zinn, A People's History of the United States (Harper & Row, 1971), 317-31

  50 Richard de Lone, Smal Futures (Carnegie Foundation, 1979).

  51 See the chapter on European social welfare programs in Harrel Rodgers, The Cost of

  Human Neglect (M. E. Sharpe, 1982).

  147

  52 Jerre Mangione, The Dream and the Deal: The Federal Writers Project 1935-1943 (Little,

  Brown, 1972).

  53 See Kai Nielsen, "Global Justice, Capitalism, and the Third World," The Journal of Applied Philosophy (1984), reprinted in Tibor R. Machan, ed.. The Main Debate (Random House, 1987).

  54 Between 1970 and 1982, according to the World Bank, the foreign debt of sub-Saharan

  Africa increased from $5.7 bil ion to $51.5 bil ion. An official of the British relief organization Oxfam was critical of the World Bank for putting pressure on these nations to use their

  resources for cash crops for export instead of for food for their own people. New York

  Times, Nov. 12, 1084.

  55 Op-ed piece. New York Times, Jan. 10, 1977.

  56 Boston Globe, Dec. 27, 1981.

  57 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Harvard University Press, 1971).

  58 Washington Post, Oct. 30, 1988.

  59 John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical," Philosophy and Public Affairs (Summer 1985), tries to clarify the points he made in his book. He says his intention was

  practical, that his conception of justice is supposed to serve as a basis of "informed and

  wil ing agreement between citizens viewed as free and equal persons." He talks about

  "public agreement in judgment on due reflection … free agreement, reconciliation through

  public reason … social cooperation on the basis of mutual respect … given a desire for free

  and uncoerced agreement, a public understanding." Through al this, there is no indication

  that such an understanding can only be reached "free and uncoerced" among that majority

  of the population that constitutes the lower and middle classes and has a pressing need for

  economic justice. There is no recognition that conflict and struggle are inevitable in the

  attempt to achieve justice, even if we try to moderate that conflict as much as possible, to

  shorten that struggle by reaching "a public understanding" among a large enough pan of the population to overwhelm the resistance of the rich and powerful.

  60 Alee Nove, professor of economics at the University of Glasgow, in his book The

  Economics of Feasible Socialism, (George Alien & Unwin, 1983), has tried to work out a common sense approach to a socialist economy. He believes scale is important—that is,

  smal enterprises wherever possible. He also thinks no one need get paid more than two or

  three times anyone else. He says, "We should envisage the degree of inequality which is

  necessary to elicit the necessary effort by free human beings… . There seems no good

  reason to make some individuals many times richer than others in order to obtain the

  necessary incentive effect," pp. 215-216.

  61 New York Times, July 12, 1988.

  62 Reeve Vanneman and Lynn Cannon, The American Perception of Class (Temple University

  Press, 1987) make an important distinction. They say it is true that the working class in the

  United States has been unsuccessful in forming its own political party or in making any

  radical changes in the economic structure of the country. But, they insist, this is not proof of

  the lack of class consciousness. What it does prove is the lack of strength of American

  workers against the enormous power of the capitalist class. After a great deal of research

  into the self-perceptions of American workers, the authors found "impressive evidence

  documenting the class consciousness of American workers was already on the record."

  63 Studs Terkel, Working (Pantheon, 1972), xi, xxi .

  148

  64 For an account of the early popular actions in the New Deal period see Maurice Hal gren,

  Seeds of Revolt (Knopf, 1934). For the strikes of the New Deal period, see Irving Bernstein, The Turbulent Years (Houghton Mifflin, 1969).

  65 See the discussion of this in Peter Irons, The New Deal Lawyers (Princeton University

  Press, 1982).

  66 Frances Piven and Richard Cloward, Poor People's Movements (Pantheon, 1977).

  67 Ibid., 264-359.

  149

  Eight

  Free Speech: Second Thoughts on the First Amendment

  Growing up in the United States, we are taught that this is a country blessed with freedom

  of speech. We learn that this is so because our Constitution contains a Bil of Rights, which

  starts off with the First Amendment and its powerful words:

  Congress shal make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or

  prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or

  of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition

  the government for a redress of grievances.

  The belief that the First Amendment guarantees our freedom of expression is part of the

  ideology of our society. Indeed, the faith in pledges written on paper and the blindness to

  political and economic realities seem strongly entrenched in that set of beliefs propagated

  by the makers of opinion in this country. We can see this in the almost religious fervor that

  accompanied the year of the Bicentennial, 200 years after the framing of the Constitution.

  In 1987, from newspapers, television, radio, from the pulpits and the classrooms, from the

  hal s of Congress, and in the statements issued by the White House, we heard praise of that

  document drawn up by the Founding Fathers. Parade magazine, read by several mil ion

  people, printed a short essay by President Ronald Reagan. In it he said,

  I can't help but marvel at the genius of our Founders ??
? . They created, with a

  sureness and originality so great and pure that I can't help but perceive the

  guiding hand of God, the first political system that insisted that power flows

  from the people to the state, not the other way around.

  That same year, the newspapers carried large advertisements for "The Constitution Bowl,"

  announced by the official Commission on the Bicentennial, to be made of "Lenox fine ivory

  China" showing the official flowers of the thirteen original states, and "bordered with pure 24 karat gold … a masterpiece worthy of the occasion." It was available for $95. A beautiful

  bowl indeed. And it was a perfect representation of the Constitution—elegant, but empty,

  capable of being fil ed with good or bad by whoever possessed the power and the resources

  to fil it.

  So it has been with the First Amendment. The First Amendment was adopted in 1791, as

  part of the Bil of Rights, in response to criticism of the Constitution when it was before the

  public for ratification. Needing nine of the thirteen states to ratify it, The Constitution was

  approved by very smal margins in three crucial states; Virginia, Massachusetts, and New

  York. Promises were made that when the first government took office, a Bil of Rights would

  be added, and so it was. Ever since then it has been hailed as the bedrock of our freedoms.

  As I am about to argue, however, to depend on the simple existence of the First

  Amendment to guarantee our freedom of expression is a serious mistake, one that can cost

  us not only our liberties but, under certain circumstances, our lives.

  “No Prior Restraint"

  The language of the First Amendment looks absolute. "Congress shal make no law …

  abridging the freedom of speech." Yet in 1798, seven years after the First Amendment was

  adopted, Congress did exactly that; it passed laws abridging the freedom of speech—the

  Alien and Sedition Acts.

  151

  The Alien Act gave the president the power to deport "al such aliens as he shal judge dangerous to the peace and safety of the United States." The Sedition Act provided that "if any person shal write, print, utter, or publish … any false, scandalous and malicious writing

  or writings against the government of the United States, or either house of the Congress of

  the U.S. or the President of the U.S., with intent to defame … or to bring either of them into

  contempt or disrepute" such persons could be fined $2,000 or jailed for two years.

  The French Revolution had taken place nine years earlier, and the new American nation,

  now with its second president, the conservative John Adams, was not as friendly to

  revolutionary ideas as it had been in 1776. Revolutionaries once in power seem to lose their

  taste for revolutions.

  French immigrants to the United States were suspected of being sympathizers of their

  revolution back home and of spreading revolutionary ideas here. The fear of them (although

  most of these French immigrants had fled the revolution) became hysterical. The newspaper

  Gazette of the United States insisted that French tutors were corrupting American children,

  "to make them imbibe, with their very milk, as it were, the poison of atheism and

  disaffection."1

  The newspaper Porcupine's Gazette said the country was swarming with "French apostles of Sedition … enough to burn al our cities and cut the throats of al the inhabitants."

  In Ireland revolutionaries were carrying on their long struggle against the English, and they

  had supporters in the United States. One might have thought that the Americans, so

  recently liberated from English rule themselves, would have been sympathetic to the Irish

  rebels. But instead, the Adams administration looked on the Irish as troublemakers, both in

  Europe and in the United States.

  Politician Harrison Gray Otis said he "did not wish to invite hordes of wild Irishmen, nor the turbulent and disorderly of al parts of the world, to come here with a view to disturb our

  tranquility, after having succeeded in the overthrow of their own governments." He worried

  that new immigrants with political ideas "are hardly landed in the United States, before they

  begin to cavil against the Government, and to pant after a more perfect state of society."2

  The Federalist party of John Adams was opposed by the Republican party of Thomas

  Jefferson. It was the beginning of the two-party system in the new nation. Their

  disagreements went back to the Constitution and the Bil of Rights, to battles in Congress

  over Hamilton's economic program. The tensions in the country were heightened at this

  time by an epidemic of yel ow fever, with discontented citizens rioting in the streets.

  Jefferson, a former ambassador to France, was friendly to the French Revolution, while

  Adams was hostile to it. President Adams, in the developing war between England and

  France, was clearly on the side of the English, and one historian has cal ed the Sedition Act

  "an internal security measure adopted during America's Half War with France."3

  Republican newspapers were delivering harsh criticism of the Adams administration. The

  newspaper Aurora in Philadelphia (edited by Benjamin Bache, the grandson of Benjamin

  Franklin) accused the president of appointing his relatives to office, of squandering public

  money, of wanting to create a monarchy, and of moving toward war. Even before the

  Sedition Act became law, Bache was arrested and charged on the basis of common law with

  libeling the president, exciting sedition, and provoking opposition to the laws.

  152

  The passage of the Sedition Act was accompanied by denunciations of the government's critics. One congressman told his col eagues, "Philosophers are the pioneers of revolution.

  They … prepare the way, by preaching infidelity, and weakening the respect of the people

  for ancient institutions. They talk of the perfectability of man, of the dignity of his nature,

  and entirely forgetting what he is, declaim perpetual y about what he should be."4 The

  statement about what man "is," could have been taken straight from Machiavel i.

  The atmosphere in the House of Representatives in those days might be said to lack some

  dignity. A congressman from Vermont, Irishman Matthew Lyon, got into a fight with

  Congressman Griswold of Connecticut. Lyon spat in Griswold's face, Griswold attacked him

  with a cane, Lyon fought back with fire tongs, and the two grappled on the floor while the

  other members of the House first watched, then separated them. A Bostonian wrote angrily

  about Lyon: "I feel grieved that the saliva of an Irishman should be left upon the face of an

  American."5

  Lyon had written an article saying that under Adams "every consideration of the public

  welfare was swal owed up in a continual grasp for power, in an unbounded thirst for

  ridiculous pomp, foolish adulation, and selfish avarice." Tried for violation of the Sedition

  Act, Lyon was found guilty and imprisoned for four months.

  The number of people jailed under the Sedition Act was not large—ten—but it is in the

  nature of oppressive laws that it takes just a handful of prosecutions to create an

  atmosphere that makes potential critics of government fearful of speaking their ful minds.

  It would seem to an ordinarily intel igent person, reading the simple, straightforward words

  of the First Amendment—"Congress shal make no law … abridging the freedom of speech,

  or of the pres
s."—that the Sedition Act was a direct violation of the Constitution. But here

  we get our first clue to the inadequacy of words on paper in ensuring the rights of citizens.

  Those words, however powerful they seem, are interpreted by lawyers and judges in a

  world of politics and power, where dissenters and rebels are not wanted. Exactly that

  happened early in our history, as the Sedition Act col ided with the First Amendment, and

  the First Amendment turned out to be poor protection.6

  The members of the Supreme Court, sitting as individual circuit judges (the new

  government didn't have the money to set up a lower level of appeals courts, as we have

  today) consistently found the defendants in the sedition cases guilty. They did it on the

  basis of English common law. Supreme Court Chief Justice Oliver El sworth, in a 1799

  opinion, said, "The common law of this country remains the same as it was before the

  Revolution."7

  That fact is enough to make us pause. English common law? Hadn't we fought and won a

  revolution against England? Were we stil bound by English common law? The answer is yes.

  It seems there are limits to revolutions. They retain more of the past than is expected by

  their fervent fol owers. English common law on freedom of speech was set down in

  Blackstone's Commentaries, a four-volume compendium of English common law. As

  Blackstone put it:

  The liberty of the press is indeed essential to the nature of a free state, but previous

  restraint upon publications, and not in criminal matter when published. Every freeman has

  an undoubted right to lay what sentiments he pleases before the public; to forbid this is to

  destroy the freedom of the press; but if he publishes what is improper, mischievous, or

  il egal, he must take the consequences of his own temerity.8

  This is the ingenious doctrine of "no prior restraint." You can say whatever you want, print whatever you want. The government cannot stop you in advance. But once you speak or

  write it, if the government decides to make certain statements "il egal," or to define them as

  "mischievous" or even just "improper," you can be put in prison.

  153

  An ordinary person, unsophisticated in the law, might respond, "You say you won't stop me from speaking my mind—no prior restraint. But if I know it wil get me in trouble, and so